Category | Template | Form |
---|---|---|
Text | Text | Text |
Author | Author | Author |
Collection | Collection | Collection |
Keywords | Keywords | Keywords |
Subpage | Subpage | Subpage |
Template | Form |
---|---|
BrowseTexts | BrowseTexts |
BrowseAuthors | BrowseAuthors |
BrowseLetters | BrowseLetters |
Template:GalleryAuthorsPreviewSmall
Special pages :
On the Question of Dialectics
Publisher: Progress Publishers
First Published: 1925 in Bolshevik, No. 5-6
The splitting of a single whole and the cognition of its contradictory parts (see the quotation from Philo on Heraclitus at the beginning of Section III, âOn Cognition,â in Lasalleâs book on Heraclitus[1]) is the essence (one of the âessentials,â one of the principal, if not the principal, characteristics or features) of dialectics. That is precisely how Hegel, too, puts the matter (Aristotle in his Metaphysics continually grapples with it and combats Heraclitus and Heraclitean ideas).
The correctness of this aspect of the content of dialectics must be tested by the history of science. This aspect of dialectics (e.g. in Plekhanov) usually receives inadequate attention: the identity of opposites is taken as the sum-total of examples [âfor example, a seed,â âfor example, primitive communism.â The same is true of Engels. But it is âin the interests of popularisation...â] and not as a law of cognition (and as a law of the objective world).
In mathematics: + and â. Differential and integral.
In mechanics: action and reaction.
In physics: positive and negative electricity.
In chemistry: the combination and dissociation of atoms.
In social science: the class struggle.
The identity of opposites (it would be more correct, perhaps, to say their âunity,ââalthough the difference between the terms identity and unity is not particularly important here. In a certain sense both are correct) is the recognition (discovery) of the contradictory, mutually exclusive, opposite tendencies in all phenomena and processes of nature (including mind and society). The condition for the knowledge of all processes of the world in their âself-movement,â in their spontaneous development, in their real life, is the knowledge of them as a unity of opposites. Development is the âstruggleâ of opposites. The two basic (or two possible? Or two historically observable?) conceptions of development (evolution) are: development as decrease and increase, as repetition, and development as a unity of opposites (the division of a unity into mutually exclusive opposites and their reciprocal relation).
In the first conception of motion, self - movement, its driving force, its source, its motive, remains in the shade (or this source is made externalâGod, subject, etc.). In the second conception the chief attention is directed precisely to knowledge of the source of âselfâ - movement.
The first conception is lifeless, pale and dry. The second is living. The second alone furnishes the key to the âself-movementâ of everything existing; it alone furnishes the key to âleaps,â to the âbreak in continuity,â to the âtransformation into the opposite,â to the destruction of the old and the emergence of the new.
The unity (coincidence, identity, equal action) of opposites is conditional, temporary, transitory, relative. The struggle of mutually exclusive opposites is absolute, just as development and motion are absolute.
NB: The distinction between subjectivism (scepticism, sophistry, etc.) and dialectics, incidentally, is that in (objective) dialectics the difference between the relative and the absolute is itself relative. For objective dialectics there is an absolute within the relative. For subjectivism and sophistry the relative is only relative and excludes the absolute. |
In his Capital, Marx first analyses the simplest, most ordinary and fundamental, most common and everyday relation of bourgeois (commodity) society, a relation encountered billions of times, viz., the exchange of commodities. In this very simple phenomenon (in this âcellâ of bourgeois society) analysis reveals all the contradictions (or the germs of all contradictions) of modern society. The subsequent exposition shows us the development (both growth and movement) of these contradictions and of this society in the ÎŁ[2] of its individual parts. From its beginning to its end.
Such must also be the method of exposition (i.e., study) of dialectics in general (for with Marx the dialectics of bourgeois society is only a particular case of dialectics). To begin with what is the simplest, most ordinary, common, etc., with any proposition: the leaves of a tree are green; John is a man: Fido is a dog, etc. Here already we have dialectics (as Hegelâs genius recognised): the individual is the universal. (cf. Aristoteles, Metaphisik, translation by Schegler, Bd. II, S. 40, 3. Buch, 4. Kapitel, 8-9: âdenn natĂŒrlich kann man nicht der Meinung sin, daĂ es ein Haus (a house in general) gebe auĂer den sichtbaren HĂ€usern,â âÎżÏ ÎłÏ ÎŹÎœ Î°Î”ÎŻÎ·ÎŒÎ”Îœ Î”ÎŻÎœÎ±ÎŻ ÏÎčΜα οίÏÎŻÎ±Îœ ÏαÏα ÏÏÏ ÏÎčÎœÎŹÏ ÎżÎŻÏίαÏâ).[3] Consequently, the opposites (the individual is opposed to the universal) are identical: the individual exists only in the connection that leads to the universal. The universal exists only in the individual and through the individual. Every individual is (in one way or another) a universal. Every universal is (a fragment, or an aspect, or the essence of) an individual. Every universal only approximately embraces all the individual objects. Every individual enters incompletely into the universal, etc., etc. Every individual is connected by thousands of transitions with other kinds of individuals (things, phenomena, processes) etc. Here already we have the elements, the germs, the concepts of necessity, of objective connection in nature, etc. Here already we have the contingent and the necessary, the phenomenon and the essence; for when we say: John is a man, Fido is a dog, this is a leaf of a tree, etc., we disregard a number of attributes as contingent; we separate the essence from the appearance, and counterpose the one to the other.
Thus in any proposition we can (and must) disclose as in a ânucleusâ (âcellâ) the germs of all the elements of dialectics, and thereby show that dialectics is a property of all human knowledge in general. And natural science shows us (and here again it must be demonstrated in any simple instance) objective nature with the same qualities, the transformation of the individual into the universal, of the contingent into the necessary, transitions, modulations, and the reciprocal connection of opposites. Dialectics is the theory of knowledge of (Hegel and) Marxism. This is the âaspectâ of the matter (it is not âan aspectâ but the essence of the matter) to which Plekhanov, not to speak of other Marxists, paid no attention.
* * *
Knowledge is represented in the form of a series of circles both by Hegel (see Logic) and by the modern âepistemologistâ of natural science, the eclectic and foe of Hegelianism (which he did not understand!), Paul Volkmann (see his Erkenntnistheorische GrundzĂŒge,[4] S.)
âCirclesâ in philosophy: [is a chronology of personsessential? No!]
Ancient: from Democritus to Plato and the dialectics of Heraclitus. Renaissance: Descartes versus Gassendi (Spinoza?) Modern: HolbachâHegel (via Berkeley, Hume, Kant). HegelâFeuerbachâMarx |
Dialectics as living, many-sided knowledge (with the number of sides eternally increasing), with an infinite number of shades of every approach and approximation to reality (with a philosophical system growing into a whole out of each shade)âhere we have an immeasurably rich content as compared with âmetaphysicalâ materialism, the fundamental misfortune of which is its inability to apply dialectics to the Bildertheorie,[5] to the process and development of knowledge.
Philosophical idealism is only nonsense from the stand-
point of crude, simple, metaphysical materialism. From the standpoint of dialectical materialism, on the other hand, philosophical idealism is a one-sided, exaggerated, ĂŒberschwengliches (Dietzgen)[6] development (inflation, distension) of one of the features, aspects, facets of knowl- edge, into an absolute, divorced from matter, from nature, | |||
apotheosised. Idealism is clerical obscurantism. True. But
philosophical idealism is (âmore correctlyâ and âin additionâ) a road to clerical obscurantism through one of the shades of the infinitely com- plex knowledge (dialectical) of man. | NB
this aphor- ism |
Human knowledge is not (or does not follow) a straight line, but a curve, which endlessly approximates a series of circles, a spiral. Any fragment, segment, section of this curve can be transformed (transformed one-sidedly) into an independent, complete, straight line, which then (if one does not see the wood for the trees) leads into the quagmire, into clerical obscurantism (where it is anchored by the class interests of the ruling classes). Rectilinearity and one-sidedness, woodenness and petrification, subjectivism and subjective blindnessâvoilĂ the epistemological roots of idealism. And clerical obscrutantism (= philosophical idealism), of course, has epistemological roots, it is not groundless; it is a sterile flower undoubtedly, but a sterile flower that grows on the living tree of living, fertile, genuine, powerful, omnipotent, objective, absolute human knowledge.
- â See p. 348 of this volumeâEd.
- â summationâEd.
- â for, of course, one cannot hold the opinion that there can be a house (in general) apart from visible houses.ââEd.
- â P. Volkmann, Erkenntnistheorische GrundzĂŒge der Naturwissenschaften, Leipzig-Berlin, 1910, p. 35.âEd.
- â theory of reflectionâEd.
- â The reference to the use by Josef Dietzgen of the term âĂŒberschwenglich,â which means: exaggerated, excessive, infinite; for example, in the book Kleinere philosophische Schriften (Minor Philosophical Writings), Stuttgart, 1903, p. 204, Dietzgen uses this term as follows: âabsolute and relative are not infinitely separated.â