Category | Template | Form |
---|---|---|
Text | Text | Text |
Author | Author | Author |
Collection | Collection | Collection |
Keywords | Keywords | Keywords |
Subpage | Subpage | Subpage |
Template | Form |
---|---|
BrowseTexts | BrowseTexts |
BrowseAuthors | BrowseAuthors |
BrowseLetters | BrowseLetters |
Template:GalleryAuthorsPreviewSmall
Special pages :
Conspectus of the Book The Holy Family by Marx and Engels
Source: Lenin Collected Works, 4th Edition, Moscow, 1976, Volume 38, pp. 19 - 51
Publisher: Progress Publishers
First Published: 1930 in Lenin Miscellany XII
THE HOLY FAMILY, OR CRITIQUE OF CRITICAL CRITICISM
AGAINST BRUNO BAUER & CO.
BY FREDERICK ENGELS AND KARL MARX
FRANKFORT-ON-MAIN
LITERARY PUBLISHING HOUSE
(J. RĂTTEN)
1845[1]
This little book, printed in octavo, consists of a foreword (pp. III-IV)[2] (dated Paris, September 1844), a table of contents (pp. V-VIII) and text proper (pp. 1-335), divided into nine chapters (Kapitel). Chapters I, II and III were written by Engels, Chapters V, VIII and IX by Marx, Chapters IV, VI and VII by both, in which case, however, each has signed the particular chapter section or subsection, supplied with its own heading, that was written by him. All these headings are satirical up to and including the âCritical Transformation of a Butcher into a Dogâ (the heading of Section 1 of Chapter VIII). Engels is responsible for pages 1-17 Chapters I, II, III and sections 1 and 2 of Chapter IV, pages 138-142 (Section 2a of Chapter VI) and pages 240-245 (Section 2b of Chapter VII):
|
The first chapters are entirely criticism of the style (t h e w h o l e ( ! ) first chapter, pp. 1-5) of the Literary Gazette [[Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung of Bruno Bauer[3]âin their foreword Marx and Engels say that their criticism is directed against its first eight numbers]], criticism of its distortion of history (Chapter II, pp. 5-12, especially of English history), criticism of its themes (Chapter III, pp. 13-14, ridiculing the GrĂŒndlichkeit[4] of the account of some dispute of Herr Nauwerk with the Berlin Faculty of Philosophy), criticism of views on love (Chapter IV, 3 by Marx), criticism of the account of Proudhon in the Literary Gazette ((IV,4) Proudhon, p. 22 u. ff. bis[5] 74. At the beginning there is a mass of corrections of the translation: they have confused formule et signification,[6] they have translated la justice as Gerechtigkeit[7] instead of Rechtpraxis,[8] etc.). This criticism of the translation (Marx entitles itâCharacterisierende Ăbersetzung No. I, II u.s.w.[9]) is followed by Kritische Randglosse No. I u.s.w.,[10] where Marx defends Proudhon against the critics of the Literary Gazette, counterposing his clearly socialist ideas to speculation.
Marxâs tone in relation to Proudhon is very laudatory (although there are minor reservations, for example reference to Engelsâ Umrisse zu einer Kritik der Nationalökonomie[11] in the Deutsch-Französische JahrbĂŒcher[12]).
Marx here advances from Hegelian philosophy to socialism: the transition is clearly observableâit is evident what Marx has already mastered and how he goes over to the new sphere of ideas.
(36) âAccepting the relations of private property as human and rational, political economy comes into continual contradiction with its basic premise, private property, a contradiction analogous to that of the theologian, who constantly gives a human interpretation to religious conceptions and by that very fact comes into constant conflict with his basic premise, the superhuman character of religion. Thus, in political economy wages appear at the beginning as the proportionate share of the product due to labour. Wages and profit on capital stand in the most friendly and apparently the most human relationship, reciprocally promoting one another. Subsequently it turns out that they stand in the most hostile relationship, in inverse proportion to each other. Value is determined at the beginning in an apparently rational way by the cost of production of an object and its social usefulness. Later it turns out that value is determined quite fortuitously, not bearing any relation to cost of production or social usefulness. The magnitude of wages is determined at the beginning by free agreement between the free worker and the free capitalist. Later it turns out that the worker is compelled to agree to the determination of wages by the capitalist, just as the capitalist is compelled to fix it as low as possible. Freedom of the contracting Parthei[13]â [this is the way the word is spelled in the book] âhas been supplanted by compulsion. The same thing holds good of trade and all other economic relations. The economists themselves occasionally sense these contradictions, and the disclosure of these contradictions constitutes the main content of the conflicts between them. When, however, the economists in one way or another become conscious of these contradictions, they themselves attack private property in any one of its private forms as the falsifier of what is in itself (i.e., in their imagination) rational wages, in itself rational value, in itself rational trade. Adam Smith, for instance, occassionally polemises against the capitalists, Destutt de Tracy against the bankers, Simonde de Sismondi against the factory system, Ricardo against landed property, and nearly all modern economists against the non-industrial capitalists, in whom private property appears as a mere consumer.
âThus, as an exceptionâand all the more so when they attack some special abuseâthe economists sometimes stress the semblance of the humane in economic relations, while, more often than not, they take these relations precisely in their marked difference from the humane, in their strictly economic sense. They stagger about within that contradiction without going beyond its limits.
âProudhon put an end to this unconsciousness once for all. He took the humane semblance of the economic relations seriously and sharply opposed it to their inhumane reality. He forced them to be in reality what they imagine themselves to be, or, more accurately, to give up their own idea of themselves and confess their real inhumanity. He therefore quite consistently represented as the falsifier of economic relations not one or another particular type of private property, as other economists have done, but private property as such, in its entirety. He has done all that can be done by criticism of political economy from the stand-point of political economy.â (39)
Herr Edgarâs reproach (Edgar of the Literary Gazette) that Proudhon makes a âgodâ out of âjustice,â Marx brushes aside by saying that Proudhonâs treatise of 1840[14] does not adopt âthe standpoint of German development of 1844â (39), that this is a general failing of the French, and that one must also bear in mind Proudhonâs reference to the implementation of justice by its negationâa reference making it possible to have done with this Absolute in history as well (um auch dieses Absoluten in der Geschichte ĂŒberhoben zu sein)âat the end of p. 39. âIf Proudhon does not arrive at this consistent conclusion, it is owing to his misfortune in being born a Frenchman and not a German.â (39-40)
Then follows Critical Gloss No. II (40-46), setting out in very clear relief Marxâs viewâalready almost fully developedâconcerning the revolutionary role of the proletariat.
...âHitherto political economy proceeded from the wealth that the movement of private property supposedly creates for the nations to an apology of private property. Proudhon proceeds from the opposite side, which political economy sophistically conceals, from the poverty bred by the movement of private property, to his conclusions negating private property. The first criticism of private property proceeds, of course, from the fact in which its contradictory essence appears in the form that is most perceptible and most glaring and most directly arouses manâs indignationâfrom the fact of poverty, of misery.â (41)
âProletariat and wealth are opposites. As such they form a single whole. They are both begotten by the world of private property. The question is what particular place each occupies within the antithesis. It is not sufficient to declare them two sides of a single whole.
âPrivate property as private property, as wealth, is compelled to maintain itself, and thereby its opposite, the proletariat, in existence. That is the positive side of the contradiction, self-satisfied private property.
âThe proletariat, on the other hand, is compelled as proletariat to abolish itself and thereby its opposite, the condition for its existence, that which makes it the proletariat, i.e. private property. That is the negative side of the contradiction, its restlessness within its very self, dissolved and self-dissolving private property.
âThe propertied class and the class of the proletariat present the same human self-alienation. But the former class feels happy and confirmed in this self-alientation, it recognises alienation as its own power, and has in it the semblance of human existence. The class of the proletariat feels annihilated in its self-alienation; it sees in it its own powerlessness and the reality of an inhuman existnece. To use an expression of Hegelâs, the class of the proletariat is in abasement indignation at this abasement, an indignation to which it is necessarily driven by the contradiction between its human nature and its conditions of life, which are the outright, decisive and comprehensive negation of that nature.
âWithin this antithesis the private property-owner is therefore the conservative side, the proletarian, the destructive side. From the former arises the action of preserving the antithesis, from the latter, that of annihilating it.
âIn any case, in its economic movement private property drives towards its own dissolution, but only through a development which does not depend on it, of which it is unconscious and which takes place against its will, through the very nature of things, only inasmuch as it produces the proletariat as proletariat, misery conscious of its spiritual and physical misery, dehumnaisation conscious of its dehumanisation and therefore self-abolishing. The proletariat executes the sentence that private property pronounced on itself by begetting the proletariat, just as it executes the sentence that wage-labour pronounced on itself by begetting wealth for others and misery for itself. When the proletariat is victorious, it by no means becomes the absolute side of society, for it is victorious only by abolishing itself and its opposite. Then the proletariat disappears as well as the opposite which determines it, private property.
âWhen socialist writers ascribe this historic role to the proletariat, it is not, as Critical Criticism would have one think, because they consider the proletarians as gods. Rather the contrary. Since the abstraction of all humanity, even of the semblance of humanity, is practically complete in the fully-formed proletariat; since the conditions of life of the proletariat sum up all the conditions of life of society today in their most inhuman and acute form; since man has lost himself in the proletariat, yet at the same time has not only gained theoretical consciousness of that loss, but through the no longer removable, no longer disguisable, absolutely imperative needâthe practical expression of necessityâis driven directly to revolt against that inhumanity; it follows that the proletariat can and must free itelf. But it cannot free itself without abolishing the conditions of its own life. It cannot abolish the conditions of its own life without abolishing all the inhuman conditions of life of society today which are summed up in its own situation. Not in vain does it go through the stern but steeling school of labour. It is not a question of what this or that proletarian, or even the whole proletariat, at the moment considers as its aim. It is a question of what the proletariat is, and what, in accordance with this being, it will historically be compelled to do. Its aim and historical action is irrevocably and clearly foreshadowed in its own life situation as well as in the whole organisation of bourgeois society today. There is no need here to show that a large part of the English and French proletariat is already conscious of its historic task and is constantly working to develop that consciousness into complete clarity.â (42-45)
CRITICAL GLOSS NO. 3
âHerr Edgar cannot be unaware that Herr Bruno Bauer
based all his arguments on âinfinite self-consciousnessâ and that he also saw in this principle the creative principle of the gospels, which, by their infinite unconsciousness, appear to be in direct contradiction to infinite self-con- sciousness. In the same way Proudhon considers equality as the creative principle of private property, which is in direct contradiction to equality. If Herr Edgar compares | ||
French equality with German self-consciousness for an in-
stant, he will see that the latter principle expresses in Ger- man, i.e., in abstract thought, what the former says in French, that is, in the language of politics and of thoughtful | ||
observation. Self-consciousness is manâs equality with
himself in pure thought. Equality is manâs consciousness of himself in the element of practice, i.e., therefore, manâs consciousness of other men as his equals and manâs attitude to other men as his equals. Equality is the French expression for the unity of human essence, for manâs consciousness of his species and his attitude towards his species, for the practical identity of man with man, i.e., for the social or human relation of man to man. As therefore destructive criticism in Germany, before it had progressed in Feuerbach to the consideration of real man, tried to solve everything definite and existing by the principle of self-consciousness, destructive criticism in France tried to do the same by the principle of equality.â (48-49) | ||
âThe opinion that philosophy is the abstract expression
of existing conditions does not belong orginally to Herr Edgar. It belongs to Feuerbach, who was the first to de- scribe philosophy as speculative and mystical empiricism, and proved it.â (49-50) | ||
ââWe always come back to the same thing... Proudhon
writes in the interests of the proletarians.â[15] He does not | ||
write in the interests of self-sufficient criticism or out of
any abstract, self-made interest, but out of a massive, real, historical interest, an interest that goes beyond crit- | ||
icism,that will go as far as a crisis. Not only does Proud-
hon write in the interests of the proletarians, he is himself a proletarian, un ouvrier. His work is a scientific manifesto of the French proletariat and therefore has quite a different historical significance from that of the literary botchwork of a Critical Critic.â (52-53) âProudhonâs desire to abolish non-owning and the old form of owning is exactly identical to his desire to abol- ish the practically alienated relation of man to his ob- jective essence, to abolish the political-economic ex- pression of human self-alienation. Since, however, his criticism of political economy is still bound by the pre- mises of political economy, the reappropriation of the ob- jective world is still conceived in the political-economic form of possession. âProudhon indeed does not oppose owning to non-owning, as Critical Criticism makes him do, but possession to the old form of owning, to private property. He declares posses- sion to be a âsocial function.â In a function, âinterestâ is not directed however toward the âexclusionâ of another, but toward setting into operation and realising my own powers, the powers of my being. âProudhon did not succeed in giving this thought appro- | ||
priate development. The concept of âequal possessionâ is a
political-economic one and therefore itself still an alienated expression for the principle that the object as being for man as the objective being of man, is at the same time the existence of man for other men, his human relation to other men, the social behaviour of man in relation to man. Proudhon abolishes political-economic estrangement within political-economic estrangement.â (54-55) | ||
[[This passage is highly characteristic, for it shows how
Marx approached the basic idea of his entire âsystem,â sit venia verbo,[16] namely the concept of the social relations of production.]] As a trifle, it may be pointed out that on p. 64 Marx devotes five lines to the fact that âCritical Criticismâ trans- lates marĂ©chal as âMarschallâ instead of âHufschmied.â[17] Very interesting are: pp. 65-67 (Marx approaches the labour theory of value); pp. 70-71 (Marx answers Edgarâs charge that Proudhon is muddled in saying that the worker cannot buy back his product), 71-72 and 72-73 (spec- ulative, idealistic, âetherealâ (Ă€therisch) socialismâand âmassâ socialism and communism). |
p. 76. | (Section 1, first paragraph: Feuerbach disclosed
real mysteries, Szeligaâvice versa.) | ||
p. 77. | (Last paragraph: anachronism of the n a ĂŻ v e relation
of rich and poor: âsi le riche le savait!â[18]) | ||
pp.79-85. | (All these seven pages are extremely interesting.
This is Section 2, âThe Mystery of Speculative Con- structionââa criticism of speculative philosophy using the well-known example of âfruitââder Fruchtâa crit- icism aimed directly a g a i n s t H e g e l as well. Here too is the extremely interesting remark that Hegel âvery oftenâ gives a real presentation, embracing the thing itselfâdie S a c h e selbstâwithin the speculative pre- sentation.) | ||
pp. 92, 93â | f r a g m e n t a r y remarks against Degradie
rung der Sinnlichkeit.[19] | ||
p. 101. | âHeâ (Szeliga) âis unable ... to see that industry | ||
and trade found universal kingdoms that are quite
different from Christianity and morality, family hap- piness and civic welfare.â | |||
p. 102. | (End of the first paragraphâbarbed remarks on the
significance of notaries in modern society.... âThe notary is the temporal confessor. He is a puritan by profes- sion, and âhonesty,â Shakespeare says, is âno puritan.â He is at the same time the go-between for all possible purposes, the manager of civil intrigues and plots.â) | ||
p. 110. | Another example of ridiculing abstract specula-
tion: the âconstructionâ of how man becomes master over beast; âbeastâ (das Tier) as an abstraction is changed from a lion into a pug, etc. | ||
p. 111. | A characteristic passage regarding EugĂšne Sue[20]:
owing to his hypocrisy towards the bourgeoisie, he ideal- ises the grisette morally, evading her attitude to mar- riage, her ânaĂŻveâ liaison with un Ă©tudiant[21] or ouv- | ||
rier.[22] âIt is precisely in that relation that sheâ (gri-
sette) âconstitutes a really human contrast to the sanc- timonious, narrow-hearted, self-seeking wife of the bourgeois, to the whole circle of the bourgeoisie, that is, to the official circle.â | |||
p. 117. | The âmassâ of the sixteenth and the nineteenth
centuries was different âvon vorn herein.â[23] | ||
pp. 118-121. | This passage (in Chapter VI: âAbsolute Cri-
tical Criticism, or Critical Criticism in the Person of Herr Bruno.â 1) Absolute Criticismâs First Campaign. a) âSpiritâ and âMassâ) is e x t r e m e l y important: a criticism of the view that history was unsuccessful owing to the interest in it by the mass and its reliance on the mass, which was satisfied with a âsuperficialâ com- prehension of the âidea.â |
âIf, therefore, Absolute Criticism condemns some-
thing as âsuperficial,â it is simply previous history, the actions and ideas of which were those of the âmasses.â It rejects mass history to replace it by critical history (see Herr Jules Faucher on Topical Questions in Eng- land[24]).â (119) | |||
âThe âideaâ always exposed itself to ridicule inso-
far as it differed from âinterest.â On the other hand, it is easy to understand that every mass âinterestâ that | NB | ||
asserts itself historically goes far beyond its real limits
in the âideaâ or âimaginationâ when it first comes on the scene, and is confused with human interest in general. This illusion constitutes what Fourier calls the tone of each historical epochâ (119)âas an illus- tration of this the example of the French Revolution (119-120) and the well-known words (1 2 0 in fine[25]): | |||
âWith the thoroughness of the historical action, the
size of the mass who perform it will therefore increase.â | NB |
How far the sharpness of Bauerâs division into Geist[26]
and Masse[27] goes is evident from this phrase that Marx attacks: âIn the mass, not somewhere else, is the true enemy of the spirit to be sought.â (121) |
Marx answers this by saying that the enemies of prog-
ress are the products endowed with independent being (verselbstĂ€ndigten) of the self-abasement of the mass, although they are not ideal but material products existing in an out- ward way. As early as 1789, Loustallotâs journal[28] had the motto: |
|
But in order to rise (122), says Marx, it is not enough
to do so in thought, in the idea. |
âYet Absolute Criticism has learnt from Hegelâs Phen-
omenology[30] at least the art of converting real objective chains that exist outside me into merely ideal, merely sub- jective chains existing merely within me, and thus of converting all exterior palpable struggles into pure struggles of thought.â (122) |
In this way it is possible to prove, says Marx bitingly,
the pre-established harmony between Critical Criticism and the censorship, to present the censor not as a police hangman (Polizeischerge) but as my own personified sense of tact and moderation. |
Preoccupied with its âGeist,â Absolute Criticism does
not investigate whether the phrase, self-deception and pithlessness (Kernlosigkeit) are not in its own empty (windig) pretensions. |
âThe situation is the same with âprogress.â In spite of
the pretensions of âprogress,â continual retrogressions and circular movements are to be observed. Far from suspecting that the category âprogressâ is completely empty and abstract, Absolute Criticism is instead so ingenious as to re- cognise âprogressâ as being absolute, in order to explain retrogression by assuming a âpersonal adversaryâ of progress, the mass.â (123-124) |
âAll communist and socialist writers proceeded from
the observation that, on the one hand, even the most favourable brilliant deeds seemed to remain without brilliant results, to end in trivialities, and, on the other, all progress of the spirit had so far been progress against the mass of mankind, driving it to an ever more dehumanised situation. They therefore declared âprogressâ (see Fourier) to be an inadequate abstract phrase; they assumed (see Owen, among others) a fundamental flaw in the civilised world; that is why they subjected the real bases of contemporary society to incisive criticism. This communist criticism immediately had its counterpart in practice in the movement of the great mass, in opposition to which the previous historical development had taken place. One must be acquainted with the studiousness, the craving for knowledge, the moral energy and the unceasing urge for development of the French and English workers to be able to form an idea of the human nobility of this movement.â (124-125) |
âWhat a fundamental superiority over the communist
writers it is not to have traced spiritlessness, indolence, superficiality and self-complacency to their origin but to have denounced them morally and exposed them as the opposite of the spirit, of progress!â (125) | ||
âThe relation between âspirit and mass,â however, has
still a hidden sense, which will be completely revealed in the course of the reasoning. We only make mention of it here. That relation discovered by Herr Bruno is, in fact, nothing but a critically caricatured culmination of Hegelâs conception of history; which, in turn, is nothing but the speculative expression of the Christian-Germanic dogma of the antithesis between spirit and matter, between God and the world. This antithesis is expressed in history, in the human world itself, in such a way that a few chosen individuals as the active spirit stand opposed to the rest of mankind, as the spiritless mass, as matter.â (126) | ||
And Marx points out that Hegelâs conception of history
(Geschichtsauffassung) presupposes an abstract and absolute spirit, the embodiment of which is the mass. Par- allel with Hegelâs doctrine there developed in France the theory of the Doctrinaires[31] (126) who proclaimed the sovereignty of reason in opposition to the sovereignty of the people in order to exclude the mass and rule alone (allein). | ||
Hegel is âguilty of a double half-heartednessâ (127):
1) while declaring that philosophy is the being of the Abso- lute Spirit, he does not declare this the spirit of the philo- sophical individual; 2) he makes the Absolute Spirit the creator of history only in appearance (nur zum Schein), only post festum,[32]only in consciousness. | ||
Bruno does away with this half-heartedness; he declares
that Criticism is the Absolute Spirit and the creator of his- tory in actual fact. | ||
âOn the one side stands the Mass, as the passive, spirit-
less, unhistorical material element of history; on the otherâ the Spirit, Criticism, Herr Bruno and Co. as the active ele- ment from which all historical action arises. The act of the transformation of society is reduced to the brain work of Critical Criticism.â (128) | ||
As the first example of âthe campaigns of Absolute Crit-
icism against the Mass,â Marx adduces Bruno Bauerâs attitude to the Judenfrage, and he refers to the refutation of Bauer[33] in Deutsch-Französische JahrbĂŒcher. | ||
âOne of the chief pursuits of Absolute Criticism consists
in first bringing all questions of the day into their right setting. For it does not answer, of course, the real questionsâbut substitutes quite different ones.... It thus distorted the âJewish question,â too, in such a way that it did not need to investigate political emancipation, which is the subject-matter of that question, but could instead be satisfied with a criticism of the Jewish religion and a des- cription of the Christian-German state. | ||
âThis method, too, like all Absolute Criticismâs original-
ities, is the repetition of a speculative verbal trick. Spec- ulative philosophy, in particular Hegelâs philosophy, must transpose all questions from the form of common sense to the form of speculative reason and convert the real question into a speculative one to be able to answer it. Having distorted my questions and having, like the cate- chism, placed its own questions into my mouth, specul lative philosophy could, of course, again like the catechism, have its ready answer to each of my questions.â (134-135) |
In Section 2a (...ââCriticismâ and âFeuerbachââDamna-
tion of Philosophy...â)âpp. 138-142âwritten by Engels, one finds Feuerbach warmly praised. In regard to âCriti- cismâsâ attacks on philosophy, its contrasting to philosophy the actual wealth of human relations, the âimmense content of history,â the âsignificance of man,â etc., etc., right up to the phrase: âthe mystery of the system revealed,â Engels says: | ||
âBut who, then, revealed the mystery of the âsystemâ?
Feuerbach. Who annihilated the dialectics of concepts, the war of the gods known to the philosophers along? Feuer- bach. Who substituted for the old rubbish and for âinfinite self-consciousnessâ not, it is true, âthe significance of manââas though man had another significance than that of being manâbut still âManâ? Feuerbach, and only Feuer- bach. And he did more. Long ago he did away with the very categories that âCriticismâ now wieldsâthe âreal wealth of human relations, the immense content of history, the struggle of history, the fight of the mass against the spirit,â etc., etc. | ||
âOnce man is conceived as the essence, the basis of all
human activity and situations, only âCriticismâ can invent new categories and transform man himself again into a category and into the principle of a whole series of categories as it is doing now. It is true that in so doing it takes the only road to salvation that remained for frightened and persecuted theological inhumanity. History does nothing, it âpossesses no immense wealth,â it âwages no battles.â It is man and not âhistory,â real living man, that does all that, that possesses and fights; âhistoryâ is not, as it were, a person apart, using man as a means to achieve its own aims; history is nothing but the activity of man pursuing his aims.If Absolute Criticism, after Feuerbachâs brilliant reasoning, still dares to reproduce the old trash in a new form...â (139-140) etc.âthen, Engels says, this fact alone is sufficient to assess the Critical naĂŻvetĂ©, etc. | ||
And after this, in regard to the opposition of Spirit
and âMatterâ (Criticism calls the mass âmatterâ), Engels says: | ||
âIs Absolute Criticism then not genuinely Christian-
German? After the old contradiction between spiritualism | ||
and materialism has been fought out on all sides and over-
come once for all by Feuerbach, âCriticismâ again makes a basic dogma of it in its ugliest form and gives the victory to the âChristian-German spirit.ââ (141) |
In regard to Bauerâs words: âTo the extent of the prog-
ress now made by the Jews in theory, they are emancipated; to the extent that they wish to be free, they are freeâ (142), Marx says: |
âFrom this proposition one can immediately measure
the critical gap which separates mass profane communism and socialism from absolute socialism. The first proposition of profane socialism rejects emancipation in mere theory as an illusion and for real freedom it demands besides the idealistic âwill,â very tangible, very material conditions. How low âthe Massâ is in comparison with holy Criticism, the Mass which considers material, practical upheavals necessary, merely to win the time and means required to deal with âtheoryâ!â (142) |
Further, (pp. 143-167), the most boring, incredibly
caviling criticism of the Literary Gazette, a sort of word by word commentary of a âblastingâ type. Absolutely noth- ing of interest. |
The end of the section ((b) The Jewish Question No. II.
pp. 142-185)âpp. 167-185 provides an interesting answer by Marx to Bauer on the latterâs defence of his book Juden- frage, which was criticised in the Deutsch-Französische JahrbĂŒcher. (Marx constantly refers to the latter.) Marx here sharply and clearly stresses the basic principles of his entire world outlook. |
âReligious questions of the day have at present a social sig-
nificanceâ (167)âthis was already pointed out in the Deutsch- Französische JahrbĂŒcher. It characterised the âreal position of Judaism in civil society today.â âHerr Bauer explains the real Jew by the Jewish religion, instead of explaining the mystery of the Jewish religion by the real Jew.â (167-168) |
Herr Bauer does not suspect âthat real, worldly Judaism,
and hence religious Judaism too, is being continually pro- duced by present-day civil life and finds its final develop- ment in the money system.â |
It was pointed out in the Deutsch-Französische Jahr-
bĂŒcher that the development of Judaism has to be sought âin der kommerziellen und industriellen Praxisâ[34] (169), âthat practical Judaism âvollendete Praxis der christlichen Welt selber ist.â[35] (169) |
âIt was proved that the task of abolishing the essence
of Judaism is in truth the task of abolishing Judaism in civil society, abolishing the inhumanity of the present-day practice of life, the summit of which is the money system. â (169) |
In demanding freedom, the Jew demands something
that in no way contradicts political freedom (172)âit is a question of political freedom. |
âHerr Bauer was shown that it is by no means contrary
to political emancipation to divide man into the non-re- ligious citizen and the religious private individual.â (172) |
And immediately following the above: |
âHe was shown that as the state emancipates itself from
religion by emancipating itself from state religion and leaving religion to itself within civil society, so the indi- vidual emancipates himself politically from religion by re- garding it no longer as a public matter but as a private matter. Finally, it was shown that the terroristic attitude of the French Revolution to religion, far from refuting this conception, bears it out.â (172) |
The Jews desire allgemeine Menschenrechte.[36] |
âIn the Deutsch-Französische JahrbĂŒcher it was
expounded to Herr Bauer that this âfree humanityâ and the ârecognitionâ of it are nothing but the recognition of the selfish, civil individual and of the uncurbed movement of the spiritual and material elements which are the content of his life situation, the content of civil life today; that the Rights of Man do not, therefore, free man from religion but give him freedom of religion; that they do not free him from property, but procure for him freedom of prop- erty; that they do not free him from the filth of gain but give him freedom of choice of a livelihood. |
âHe was shown that the recognition of the Rights
of Man by the modern state means nothing more than did the recognition of slavery by the ancient state. In fact, just as the ancient state had slavery as its natural basis, the modern state has civil society and the man of civil society, i.e., the independent man connected with other men only by the ties of private interest and uncon- scious natural necessity, the slave of labour for gain and of his own as well as other menâs selfish need. The mo- dern state has recognised this as its natural basis as such in the universal Rights of Man.â[37] (175) |
âThe Jew has all the more right to the recognition of
his âfree humanityââ âas âfree civil societyâ is of a thoroughly commercial and Jewish nature and the Jew is a necessary link in it.â (176) | ||
That the âRights of Manâ are not inborn, but arose histor-
ically, was known already to Hegel. (176) | ||
Pointing out the contradictions of constitutionalism,
âCriticismâ does not generalise them (faĂt nicht den allge- meinen Widerspruch des Constitutionalismus[38]). (177-178) If it had done so, it would have proceeded from constitu- tional monarchy to the democratic representative state, to the perfect modern state. (178) | ||
Industrial activity is not abolished by the abolition
of privileges (of the guilds, corporations, etc.); on the con- trary it develops more strongly. Property in land is not abolished by the abolition of privileges of landownership, âbut, rather, first begins its universal movement with the abolition of its privileges and through the free division and free alienation of land.â (180) | ||
Trade is not abolished by the abolition of trade privileges
but only then does it become genuinely free trade, so also | ||
with religion, âso religion develops in its practical univer-
sality only where there is no privileged religion (one calls to mind the North American States).â | ||
...âPrecisely the slavery of bourgeois society is in ap-
pearance the greatest freedom....â (181) | ||
To the dissolution (Auflösung) (182) of the political
existence of religion (the abolition of the state church),
for electors), etc.âcorresponds their âmost vigorous life, which now obeys its own laws undisturbed and develops into its full scope.â | ||
Anarchy is the law of bourgeois society emancipated
from privileges. (182-183) |
... C) CRITICAL BATTLE AGAINST
THE FRENCH REVOLUTION
âThe ideasââMarx quotes Bauerââwhich the French
Revolution gave rise to did not, however, lead beyond the order that it wanted to abolish by force. | ||
âIdeas can never lead beyond an old world order but
only beyond the ideas of the old world order. Ideas cannot carry anything out at all. In order to carry out ideas men are needed who dispose of a certain practical force.â (186) | ||
The French Revolution gave rise to the ideas of communism
(Babeuf), which, consistently developed, contained the idea of a new Weltzustand.[39]
check the separate egotistic atoms, Marx says (188-189) that the members of civil society are, properly speaking, by no means atoms, but only imagine themselves to be such, for they are not self-sufficient like atoms, but depend on other persons, their needs continually forcing this dependence upon them.
properties, however alienated they may seem to be, and interest that hold the members of civil society together; civil, not political life is their real tie.... Only political superstition still imagines today that civil life must be held together by the state, whereas in reality, on the contrary, the state is held together by civil life.â (189)
confused the ancient realistically-democratic society, based on slavery, with the modern, spiritualistically-democratic representative state, based on bourgeois society. Before his execution Saint-Just pointed to the table (Tabelle a poster? hanging) of the Rights of Man and said: âCâest pourtant moi qui ai fait cela.â[40] âThis very table proclaimed the rights of a man who cannot be the man of the ancient republic any more than his economic and industrial relations are those of the ancient times.â (192)
but the liberal bourgeoisie became the prey of Napoleon. After the fall of Robespierre, under the Directorate, the prosaic realisation of bourgeois society begins: Sturm | ||
und Drang[42] of commercial enterprise, the whirl (Taumel)
of the new bourgeois life; âreal enlightenment of the land of France, the feudal structure of which had been smashed by the hammer of revolution, and which the numerous new owners in their first feverish enthusiasm now put under all-round cultivation; the first movements of an industry that had become freeâthese are a few of the signs of life of the newly arisen bourgeois society.â (192-193) |
CHAPTER VI. ABSOLUTE CRITICAL CRITICISM,
OR CRITICAL CRITICISM
IN THE PERSON OF HERR BRUNO
. . . 3) ABSOLUTE CRITICISMâS THIRD CAMPAIGN. . .
d) CRITICAL BATTLE AGAINST FRENCH MATERIALISM
(195-211)
[[This chapter (subsection d in the third section of Chap-
ter VI) is one of the most valuable in the book. Here there is absolutely no word by word criticism, but a completely positive exposition. It is a short sketch of the history of French materialism. Here one ought to copy out the whole chapter, but I shall limit myself to a short summary of of the contents.]]
French materialism are not only a struggle against the exist- ing political institutions, but equally an open struggle against the metaphysics of the seventeenth century, namely, | ||
against the metaphysics of Descartes, Malebranch, Spin-
oza and Leibnitz. âPhilosophy was opposed to metaphys- ics as Feuerbach, in his first decisive attack on Hegel, opposed sober philosophy to drunken speculation.â (196) | ||
The metaphysics of the seventeenth century, defeated by
the materialism of the eighteenth century, underwent a vic- torious and weighty (gehaltvolle) restoration in German phi- losophy, especially in speculative German philosophy of the nineteenth century. Hegel linked it in a masterly fashion with the whole of metaphysics and with German idealism, and he founded ein metaphysisches Universalreich.[43] This was fol- lowed again by an âattack on speculative metaphysics and metaphysics in general. It will be defeated for ever by mater- ialism, which has now been perfected by the work of specu- lation itself and coincides with humanism. Just as Feuerbach in the theoretical field, French and English socialism and co- mmunism in the practical field represented materialism coin- ciding with humanism.â (196-197) There are two trends of French materialism: 1) from Des- cartes, 2) from Locke. The latter mĂŒndet direkt in den Soc- ialismus.[44] (197) The former, mechanical materialism, turns into French nat- ural science. Descartes in his physics declares matter the only sub- stance. Mechanical French materialism takes over Descartesâ physics and rejects his metaphysics. âThis school begins with the physician Le Roy, reaches its zenith with the physician Cabanis, and the physician Lamet- trie is its centre.â (198) Descartes was still living when Le Roy transferred the mechanical structure of animals to man and declared the soul to be a modus of the body, and ideas to be mechanical movements. (198) Le Roy even thought that Descartes had concealed his real opinion. Descartes protested. At the end of the eighteenth century Cabanis perfected Cartesian materialism in his book Rapports du physique et du moral de lâhomme.[45] From the very outset the metaphysics of the seventeenth century had its adversary in materialism. DescartesâGas- sendi, the restorer of Epicurean materialism, in Englandâ Hobbes. Voltaire (199) pointed out that the indifference of the Frenchmen of the eighteenth century to the disputes of the Jesuits and others was due less to philosophy that to Lawâs financial speculations. The theoretical movement towards materialism is explained by the practical Gestaltung[46]of French life at that time. Materialistic theories corresponded to materialistic practice. The metaphysics of the seventeenth century (Descartes, Leibnitz) was still linked with a positive (positivem) content. It made discoveries in mathematics, physics, etc. In the eighteenth century the positive sciences became separated from it and metaphysics war fad geworden.[47] In the year of Malebrancheâs death, HelvĂ©tius and Cond- illac were born. (199-200) Pierre Bayle, through his weapon of scepticism, theore- tically undermined seventeenth-century metaphysics. He re- futed chiefly Spinoza and Leibnitz. He proclaimed atheistic society. He was, in the words of a French writer, âthe last metaphysician in the seventeenth-century sense of the word and the first philosopher in the sense of the eighteenth cen- tury.â (200-201) This negative refutation required a positive, anti-meta- physical system. It was provided by Locke. Materialism is the son of Great Britain. Its scholastic Duns Scotus had already raised the question: âob die Materie nicht denken könne?â[48]He was a nominalist. Nominalism is in general the first expression of material- ism.[49] The real founder of English materialism was Bacon. (âThe first and most important of the inherent qualities of matter is motion, not only as mechanical and mathematical movement, but still more as impulse, vital spirit, tension, or ... the throes (Qual) ... of matter.ââ202) âIn Bacon, its first creator, materialism has still concealed within it a naĂŻve way the germs of all-round development. Matter smiles at man as a whole with poetical sensuous brightness.â In Hobbes, materialism becomes one-sided, menschen- feindlich, mechanisch.[50] Hobbes systematised Bacon, but he did not develop (begrĂŒndet) more deeply Baconâs fund- amental principle: the origin of knowledge and ideas from the world of the senses (Sinnenwelt).âP. 203. Just as Hobbes did away with the theistic prejudices of Baconâs materialism, so Collins, Dodwell, Coward, Hartley, Priestley, etc., destroyed the last theological bounds of Lockeâs sensualism.[51] Condillac directed Lockeâs sensualism against seven- teenth-century metaphysics; he published a refutation of the systems of Descartes, Spinoza, Leibnitz, and Malebranche. The French âcivilisedâ (205) the materialism of the English. In HelvĂ©tius (who also derives from Locke), materialism was given a properly French character. Lamettrie is a combination of Cartesian and English mat- erialism. Robinet has the most connection with metaphysics. âJust as Cartesian materialism passes into natural sci- ence proper, the other trend of French materialism flows directly into socialism and communism.â (206) Nothing is easier than to derive socialism from the premis- es of materialism (reconstruction of the world of the sensesâ linking private and public interestsâdestroying the Geburts- stĂ€tten[52] of crime, etc.). Fourier proceeds immediately from the teaching of the French materialists. The Babouvists[53] were crude, immature materialists. Bentham based his system on the morality of HelvĂ©tius, while Owen takes Benthamâs system as his starting- point for founding English communism. Cabet brought com- munist ideas from England into France (populĂ€rste wenn auch flachste[54] representative of communism) 208. The âmore scientificâ are DĂ©zamy, Gay, etc., who developed the teach- ing of materialism as real humanism. On pp. 209-211 Marx gives in a note (two pages of small print) extracts from HelvĂ©tius, Holbach and Bentham, in or- der to prove the connection of the materialism of the eight- eenth century with English and French communism of the nineteenth century. Of the subsequent sections the following passage is worth noting: âThe dispute between Strauss and Bauer over Substance and Self-Consciousness is a dispute within Hegelian speculation. In Hegel there are three elements: Spinozaâs Substance, Fichteâs Self-Consciousness, and Hegelâs ne- cessary and contradictory unity of the two, the Absolute Spirit. The first element is metaphysically disguised nature in separation from man; the second is metaphysically disguised spirit in separation from nature; the third is the metaphysical- ly disguised unity of both, real man and the real human raceâ (220), and the paragraph with its assessment of Feuer- bach: âIn the domain of theology, Strauss quite consistently expounded Hegel from Spinozaâs point of view, and Bauer did the same from Fichteâs point of view. Both criticised Hegel insofar as with him each of the two elements was falsified by the other, while they carried each of the elements to its one-sided and hence consistent development.âBoth of them therefore go beyond Hegel in their Criticism, but both of them also remain within the framework of his specu- lation and each represents only one side of his system. Feuer- | ||
bach was the first to bring to completion and criticise Hegel
from Hegelâs point of view, by resolving the metaphysical Absolute Spirit into âreal man on the basis of nature,â and the first to bring to completion the Criticism of religion by sketching in a masterly manner the general basic features of the Criticism of Hegelâs speculation and hence of every kind of metaphysics.â (220-221) | ||
Marx ridicules Bauerâs âtheory of self-consciousnessâ on
account of its idealism (the sophisms of absolute idealismâ 222), points out that this is a periphrasing of Hegel, and quotes the latterâs Phenomenology and Feuerbachâs criti- cal remarks (from Philosophie der Zukunft,[55] p. 35, that philosophy negatesânegiert â the âmaterially sensuous,â just as theology negates ânature tainted by original sinâ). |
The following chapter (VII) again begins with a series of
highly boring, caviling criticisms [1). Pp. 228-235]. In section 2a there is an interesting passage.
presentative of the Mass,â who calls for the study of reality, of natural science and industry (236), and who on that account was reviled by âcriticismâ:
tive of the Mass,ââdo you think that the knowledge of his- torical reality is already complete? Or (!) do you know | |||||
of any single period in history which is actually known?â
âOr does Critical CriticismââMarx repliesââbelieve that it has reached even the beginning of a knowledge of histori- cal reality so long as it excludes from the historical move- ment the theoretical and practical relation of man to na- ture, natural science and industry? Or does it think that it actually knows any period without knowing, for example, the industry of that period, the immediate mode of pro- duction of life itself? True, spiritualistic, theological Crit- ical Criticism only knows (at least it imagines it knows) the major political, literary and theological acts of his- tory. Just as it separates thinking from the senses, the soul from the body and itself from the world, it separates history from natural science and industry and sees the origin of history not in vulgar material production on the earth but in vaporous clouds in the heavens.â (238) | No-
ta be- ne | ||||
Criticism dubbed this representative of the mass a mas-
senhafter Materialist.[56] (239) âThe criticism of the French and the English is not an abs- tract, preternatural personality outside mankind; it is the real human activity of individuals who are active members of society and who as human beings suffer, feel, think and act. That is why their criticism is a the same time practical, their communism a socialism in which they give practical, tangible measures, and in which they do not only think but even more act; it is the living real criticism of existing society, the discov- ery of the causes of âdecayâ.â (244) [[The whole of Chapter VII (228-257), apart from the pas- sages quoted above, consists only of the most incredible capti- ous criticisms and mockery, noting contradictions of the most petty character, and ridiculing each and every stupidity in the Literary Gazette, etc.]] In Chapter VIII (258-333) we have a section on the âCrit- ical Transformation of a Butcher into a Dogââand further on E u g Ăš n e S u e â s Fleur de Marie[57] (evidently a novel with this title or the heroine of some novel or other) with certain âradicalâ but uninteresting observations by Marx. Worth mentioning perhaps are only p. 2 8 5 [58] â against EugĂšne Sueâs defence of the prison cell system (Cellularsystem). âThe mystery of thisâ (305) (there was a quotation from Anekdota[59] above) âcourage of Bauerâs is Hegelâs Phenom- enology. Since Hegel here puts self-consciousness in the place of man, the most varied human reality appears only as a definite form, as a determination of self-consciousness. But a mere determination of self-consciousness is a âpure category,â a mere âthoughtâ which I can consequently also transcend in âpureâ thought and overcome through pure | |||||
thought. In Hegelâs Phenomenology the material, sensuous,
objective bases of the various alienated forms of human self-consciousness are left as they are. The whole destructive work results in the most conservative philosophy [sic!] because it thinks it has overcome the objective world, the sensuously real world, by merely transforming it into | |||||
a âthing of thought,â a mere determination of self-con-
sciousness, and can therefore dissolve its opponent, which has become ethereal, in the âether of pure thought.â The Phenomenology is therefore quite consistent in ending by re- placing all human reality by âAbsolute Knowledgeâ â Knowledge, because this is the only mode of existence of self-consciousness, and because self-consciousness is con- sidered as the only mode of existence of man;âAbsolute Knowledge for the very reason that self-consciousness knows only itself and is no more disturbed by any objective world. Hegel makes man the man of self-consciousness instead of making self-consciousness the self-consciousness of man, of the real man, and therefore of man living also in a real objec- tive world and determined by that world. He stands the world on its head and can therefore in his head dissolve all limita- tions, which nevertheless, of course, remain in existence for e- vil sensuousness, for real man. Moreover, everything which betrays the limitations of general self-consciousnessâ all sensuousness, reality, individuality of men and of their worldâ is neccessarily held by him to be a limit. The whole of the Phe- nomenology is intended to prove that self-consciousness is the only reality and all reality....â (306) | |||||
...âFinally, it goes without saying that if Hegelâs Phe-
nomenology, in spite of its speculative original sin, gives in many instances the elements of a true description of hu- man relations, Herr Bruno and Co., on the other hand, provide only an empty caricature....â (307) |
âThereby Rudolph unconsciously revealed the mystery,
long ago exposed, that human misery itself, the infinite ab- jectness which is obliged to receive alms, has to serve as a plaything to the aristocracy of money and education to satisfy their self-love, tickle their arrogance and amuse them. âThe numerous charitable associations in Germany, the numerous charitable societies in France and the great num- ber of charitable quixotic societies in England, the concerts, balls, plays, meals for the poor and even public subscriptions for victims of accidents have no other meaning.â (309-310) And Marx quotes from EugĂšne Sue: âAh, Madame, it is not enough to have danced for the be- nefit of these poor Poles.... Let us be philanthropic to the end.... Let us have supper now for the benefit of the poor!â[60] (310) On pp. 312-313 quotations f r o m F o u r i e r (adultery is good tone, infanticide by the victims of seduction â a vicious circle.... âThe degree of emancipation of woman is the natural measure of general emancipation....â (312) Civ- ilisation converts every vice from a simple into a complex, am- biguous, hypocritical form), and Marx adds: | ||
âIt is superfluous to contrast to Rudolphâs thoughts
Fourierâs masterly characterisation of marriage[61] or the | ||
works of the materialist section of French communism.â (313)
P. 313 u. ff., against the political-economic projects of EugĂšne Sue and Rudolph (presumably the hero of Sueâs novel?), projects for the association of rich and poor, and the organisation of labour (which the state ought to do), etc.âe.g., also the Armenbank[62] [7)âb) âThe bank for the Poorâ pp. 314-318] = interest-free loans to the unem- ployed. Marx takes the f i g u r e s of the project and exposes their meagreness in relation to need. And the idea of an Armenbank, says Marx, is no better than Sparkas- sen[63]..., i.e., die Einrichtung[64] of the bank ârests on the delusion that only a different distribution of wages is needed for the workers to be able to live through the whole year.â (316-317) Section c) âModel Farm at Bouquevalâ 318-320, Ru- dolphâs project for a model farm, which was praised by âCriticism,â is subjected to devastating criticism: Marx de- clares it to be a utopian project, for on the average one Frenchman gets only a quarter of a pound of meat per day, only 93 francs in annual income, etc.; in the project they work twice as much as before, etc., etc. ((Not interesting.)) | ||
320: âThe miraculous means by which Rudolph accomp-
lishes all his redemptions and marvellous cures is not his fine words but his ready money. That is what the moralists are like, says Fourier. One must be a millionaire to be able to imitate their heroes. |
âMorality is âImpuissance mise en action.â[65] Every time
it fights a vice it is defeated. And Rudolph does not even rise to the standpoint of independent morality based at least on the consciousness of human dignity. On the contrary, his morality is based on the consciousness of human weakness. He represents theological morality.â (320-321) ...âAs in reality all differences boil down more and more to the difference between poor and rich, so in the idea do all aristocratic differences become resolved into the opposi- tion between good and evil. This distinction is the last form that the aristocrat gives to his prejudices....â (323-324) ...âEvery movement of his soul is of infinite importance to Rudolph. That is why he constantly observes and appraises them....â (Examples.) âThis great lord is like the members of âYoung England,â who also wish to reform the world, to perform noble deeds, and are subject to similar hysterical fits....â (326) |
|
- â The Holy Family, or Critique of Critical Criticism. Against Bruno Bauer and Co.âthe first joint work of Karl Marx and Frederick Engels. It was written between September and November 1844 and was published in February 1845 in Frankfort-on-Main.
- â Engels, F. und Marx, K., Die heilige Familie, oder Kritik der kritischen Kritik, Frankfurt a. M., 1845. âEd.
- â Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung (General Literary Gazette)âa German monthly published in Charlottenburg from December 1843 to October 1844 by Bruno Bauer, the Young Hegelian.
- â pedantic thoroughnessâEd.
- â und folgende bisâand following up toâEd.
- â formula and significanceâEd.
- â justiceâEd.
- â juridical practiceâEd.
- â characterising translation No. I, II, etc.âEd.
- â critical gloss No. I, etc.âEd.
- â Umrisse zu einer Kritik der Nationalökonomie (Outlines of a Critique of Political Economy) was first published by Engels at the beginning of 1844 in Deutsch-Französische JahrbĂŒcher (Franco-German Annals)âsee Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844. Moscow, 1959, pp. 175-209.
- â Deutsch-Französische JahrbĂŒcher (Franco-German Annals)âa magazine published in German in Paris and edited by Karl Marx and Arnold Ruge. The only issue to appear was a double number published in February 1844. It included Marxâs articles âA Critique of the Hegelian Philosophy of Law (Introduction)â and âOn the Jewish Question,â and also Engelsâ articles âOutlines of a Critique of Political Economyâ and âThe Position of England. Thomas Carlyle. âPast and Presentâ.â These works mark the final transition of Marx and Engels to materialism and communism. Publication of the magazine was discontinued chiefly as a result of the basic differences between Marxâs views and the bourgeois-radical views of Ruge.
- â partyâEd.
- â This refers to Proudhonâs work of 1840 Quâest-ce que la propriĂ©tĂ© ou Recherches sur le principe du droit et du gouvernement (What Is Property? or Studies on the Principle of Law and Government). Marx presents a critique of this work in a letter to Schweitzer dated January 24, 1865 (see Marx and Engels, Selected Correspondence, Moscow, 1955, pp. 185-192).
- â Marx is quoting Edgar.
- â if the word may be allowedâEd.
- â blacksmithââEd.
- â if the rich only knew it!ââEd.
- â debasing of sensuousnessâEd.
- â This refers to EugĂšne Sueâs novel Les mystĂšres de Paris (Mysteries of Paris), which was written in the spirit of petty-bourgeois sentimentality. It was published in Paris in 1842-43 and very popular in France and abroad.
- â a studentâEd.
- â workerâEd.
- â from the outsetââEd.
- â Marx is referring here to articles by Jules Faucher entitled Englische Tagesfragen (Topical Questions in England), which were published in Nos. VII and VIII (June and July 1844) of the Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung.
- â at the endâEd.
- â spiritâEd.
- â massâEd.
- â Loustallotâs journal of 1789âa weekly publication entitled RĂ©volutions de Paris (Parisian Revolutions), which appeared in Paris from July 1789 to February 1794. Until September 1790 it was edited by ElisĂ©e Loustallot, a revolutionary publicist.
- â The great only seem great to usBecause we are on our knees.Let us rise!âEd.
- â PhĂ€nomenologie des Geistes (Phenomenology of Mind) by G. W. F. Hegel was first published in 1807. In working on The Holy Family, Marx made use of Vol. II of the second edition of Hegelâs works (Berlin, 1841). He called this first large work of Hegel, in which the latterâs philosophical system was elaborated, âthe source and secret of Hegelâs philosophy.â
- â Doctrinairesâmembers of a bourgeois political grouping in France during the period of the Restoration (1815-30). As constitutional monarchists and rabid enemies of the democratic and revolutionary movement, they aimed to create in France a bloc of the bourgeoisie and landed aristocracy after the English fashion. The most celebrated of the Doctrinaires were Guizot, a historian, and Royer-Collard, a philosopher. Their views constituted a reaction in the field of philosophy against the French materialism of the 18th century and the democratic ideas of the French bourgeois revolution (see Holy Family ch.VI 3. d.).
- â after the eventâEd.
- â The refutation of the views expounded by Bruno Bauer in his book Die Judenfrage (The Jewish Question), Braunschweig, 1843, was made by Marx in an article entitled âZur Judenfrageâ (âOn the Jewish Questionâ), published in 1844 in Deutsch-Französische JahrbĂŒcher.
- â in commercial and industrial practiceââEd.
- â is the perfected practice of the Christian world itselfââEd.
- â the universal rights of manâEd.
- â The Universal Rights of Manâthe principles enunciated in the âDeclaration of the Rights of Man and the Citizenâ and proclaimed during the time of the French bourgeois revolution of 1789-93.
- â does not conceive the general contradiction of constitutionalismâEd.
- â world orderâEd.
- â Yet it was I who made that.ââEd.
- â The 18th Brumaire (9 November 1799)âthe day of the coup dâĂ©tat of Napoleon Bonaparte, who overthrew the Directorate and established his own dictatorship.
- â Storm and stressâEd.
- â a metaphysical universal kingdomâEd.
- â flows directly into socialismâEd.
- â Cartesian materialismâthe materialism of the followers of Descartes (from the Latin spelling of DescartesâCartesius). The indicated bookâRapports du physique et du moral de lâhomme (Relation of the Physical to the Spiritual in Man) by P. J. G. Cabanisâwas published in Paris in 1802.
- â mouldâEd.
- â became insipidâEd.
- â whether matter can think?ââEd.
- â Nominalismâthe trend in medieval philosophy that considered general concepts as merely the names of single objects in contrast to medieval ârealism,â which recognised the existence of general concepts or ideas independent of things.
- â misanthropic, mechanicalâEd.
- â Sensualismâthe philosophical doctrine that recognises sensation as the sole source of cognition.
- â sourcesâEd.
- â Babouvistsâadherents of Gracchus Babeuf, who in 1796 led a utopian communist movement of âequalsâ in France.
- â the most popular, though most superficialâEd.
- â Lenin is referring to Feuerbachâs GrundsĂ€tze der Philosophie der Zukunft (Principles of the Philosophy of the Future), 1843, which constitutes a continuation of the latterâs aphorisms VorlĂ€ufige Thesen zu einer Reform der Philosophie (Preliminary Theses on the Reform of Philosophy), 1842, in which the author expounds the basis of his materialist philosophy and criticises Hegelâs idealist philosophy.
- â mass materialistâEd.
- â Fleur de Marieâheroine of EugĂšne Sueâs novel Mysteries of Paris.
- â â ©
- â Anekdota zur neuesten deutschen Philosophie und Publizistik. Von Bruno Bauer, Ludwig Feuerbach, Friedrich Köppen, Karl Nauwerk, Arnold Ruge und einigen Ungenannten (Unpublished Recent German Philosophical and Other Writings of Bruno Bauer, Ludwig Feuerbach, Friedrich Köppen, Karl Nauwerk, Arnold Ruge and Several Anonymous Writers)âa collection of articles that were banned for publication in German magazines. It was published in 1843 in Zurich by Ruge and included Marx as one of its contributors.
- â criminal justice and justice for virtue!âEd.
- â playthingâEd.
- â bank for the poorâEd.
- â savings-banksâEd.
- â the institutionâEd.
- â impotence in actionââEd.
- â Tory philanthropistsâa literary-political groupââYoung England.â