Category | Template | Form |
---|---|---|
Text | Text | Text |
Author | Author | Author |
Collection | Collection | Collection |
Keywords | Keywords | Keywords |
Subpage | Subpage | Subpage |
Template | Form |
---|---|
BrowseTexts | BrowseTexts |
BrowseAuthors | BrowseAuthors |
BrowseLetters | BrowseLetters |
Template:GalleryAuthorsPreviewSmall
Special pages :
Conspectus of Lassalle’s Book The Philosophy of Heraclitus the Obscure of Ephesus
Publisher: Progress Publishers
First Published: 1930 in Lenin Miscellany XII Published according to the manuscript
Conspectus of Lassalle’s book “Die Philosophie Herakleitos des Dunklen von Ephesos.” Berlin, 1858 (The Philosophy of Heraclitus the Obscure of Ephesus, Berlin, 1858) is contained in a notebook following the note on Lipps’ book Natural Science and World Outlook. Following the conspectus of Lassalle’s book, there is a fragment in the note book entitled “On the Question of Dialectics.”
The Philospohy of Heraclitus the Obscure of Ephesus
F. LASSALLE.
THE PHILOSOPHY OF HERACLITUS
THE OBSCURE OF EPHESUS,
TWO VOLUMES,
BERLIN, 1858 (pp. 379 + 479)
(Bern: Log. 119. 1)
In the epigraph, inter alia, from Hegel—from his History of Philosophy—that there is not a single proposition of Heraclitus that he would not have adopted in his Logic.
| |
One can understand why Marx called
this work of Lassalle’s “schoolboyish” (see the letter to Engels of...[3]): Lassalle simply repeats Hegel, copies from him, re-echo-ing him a million times with regard to isolated passages from Heraclitus, furnish- ing his opus with an incredible heap of learned ultra-pedantic ballast. The difference with respect to Marx: In Marx there is a mass of new material, and what interests him is only the move- ment forward from Hegel and Feuer- bach further, from idealistic to mate- rialistic dialectics. In Lassalle there is a rehash of Hegel on the particular theme selected: essentially transcribing from He- gel with respect to quotations from Hera- clitus and about Heraclitus. Lassafle divided his work into two parts: “General Part. Introduction” (Vol. I, pp. 1-68), and “Historical Part. Fragments and Evidence” (the remainder). Chapter III in the general part: “Short Logical Development of the System of Heraclitus” (pp. 45-68)—gives the quintessence of the method, of Lassalle’s conclusions. This chapter is sheer plagiarism, slavish repe- tition of Hegel concerning Heraclitus! Here too (and still more in the historical part) there is a mass of erudition, but it is eru- dition of the lowest kind: the exercise set was to seek out the Hegelian element in Heraclitus. The Strebsamer[4] pupil per- forms it “brilliantly,” reading through everything about Heraclitus in all the ancient (and modern) authors, and putting a Hegelian construction on everything. Marx in 1844-47 went from Hegel to Feuerbach, and further beyond Feuer- bach to historical (and dialectical) mate- rialism. Lassalle in 1846 began (Preface, p. III), in 1855 resumed, and in August 1857 (Preface, p. XV) finished a work of sheer, empty, useless, “learned” rehash- ing of Hegelianism!! Some chapters of the second part are interesting and not without use solely for the translations of fragments from Her- aclitus and for the popularisation of He- gel, but that does not do away with all the above-mentioned defects. The philosophy of the ancients and of Heraclitus is often quite delightful in its childish naïveté, e.g., p. 162—“how is it to be explained that the urine of persons who have eaten garlic[5] smells of garlic?” and the answer: “is it not that, as some of the fol- lowers of Heraclitus say, one and the same fiery process of transformation takes place both in the universe and in (organic) bodies, and then after cooling appears there (in the universe) as moisture, and here takes the form of urine, but the transformation (άνδανμίδσις[6]) from the food causes the smell of that from which it has arisen by mixing with it?...” (162-163) On p. 221 ff.[7] Lassalle quotes Plu- tarch, who says with regard to Heraclitus: | ||||||||
“in the same way as everything is created
by transformation out of fire, so also fire out of everything, just as we obtain things | Heraclitus on
gold and commodities | |||||||
for gold and gold for things....” In this connection, Lassalle writes about
value (Wert) (p. 223 N B) |and about Function des Geldes|[8], expounding it in the Hegelian manner (as “separated | ||||||||
abstract unity”) and adding: ...“that this
unity, money, is not something actual, but something merely ideal (Lassalle’s italics) is evident from the fact,” etc. | incorrect
(Lassalle’s idealism) | |||||||
(But all the same NB that this was
written in a book that appeared in 1858, the preface being dated August 1857.) In note 3 on p. 224 (pp. 224-225) Las- salle speaks in still greater detail about money, saying that Heraclitus was no “po- litical economist,” that money is ((only(??))) a Wertzeichen,[9] etc., etc. (“all money is merely the ideal unity or expression of value of all real products in circulation”) (224), etc.
a long passage from Plutarch, proving further (convincingly) that it is indeed Heraclitus who is referred to, and that Plu- tarch here expounds “the basic features of the speculative theology of Heraclitus” (p. 228). The passage is a good one: it conveys the spirit of Greek philosophy, the na- ïveté, profundity, the flowing transitions.
in the famous formula (or aphorism) of Heraclitus: “it is impossible to bathe twice in the same river”—actually, how- ever (as had already been said by Cratylus, a disciple of Heraclitus), it cannot be done even once (for before the whole body has entered the water, the latter is already not the same as before). (NB:) This Cratylus reduced Heraclitus’ dialectics to sophistry, pp. 294-295 and many others, by saying: nothing is true, nothing can be said about anything. A neg- ative (and merely negative) conclusion from dialectics. Heraclitus, on the other hand, had the principle: “everything is true,” there is (a part of) truth in everything. Cra- tylus merely “wagged his finger” in answer to everything, thereby showing that everything moves, that nothing can be said of anything.
to Heraclitus (λόγος,[11] sometimes είμαρ- μένη[12]), is “the law of transformation into the opposite” (p. 327) (= ένγντιοτροπή, έναντιοδρομία). Lassalle expounded the meaning of είμαρμένη as the “law of development” (p. 333), quoting, inter alia, the words of Nemesius: “Democritus, Her- aclitus and Epicurus assume that neither for the universal nor for the particular does foresight exist” (ibidem). | ||||||||
And the words of Heraclitus: “The world
was created by none of the Gods or men, but is eternally living fire and will al- ways be so” (ibidem). | ||||||||
| ||||||||
...“that it” (die Lehre[13]), “like that of the Stoics, derives everything from the world, and brings it into the world, but does not believe that any- thing came from God.” (334) An exam- | NB | |||||||
ple of “touching up” as Hegelian: Lassalle translates the famous passage of Heraclitus (according to Stobaeus) on “Das Eine Weise”[14] (έν σοφόν) as follows: | ||||||||
“However many discourses I have
heard, no one has succeeded in recog- nising that the wise is that which is separated from all (i.e., from all that exists)” (344) —considering that the words “beast or god” are an insertion, and rejecting the translations of Ritter (“wisdom is remote from all”) (344) and Schleier- macher “the wise is separated from all,” in the sense of “cognition” dis- tinct from the knowledge of partic- ulars. According to Lassalle the meaning of this passage is as follows: that “the absolute (the wise) is alien to all sensuous determinate being, that it is the negative” (349)—i.e., Nega- tive = the principle of negation, the principle of motion. A clear misrep- resentation as Hegelian! Reading He- gel into Heraclitus.
358)... this, Lassalle says, is in the sense of the unity of being and nothing. Time is the pure unity of Being and not-Be- ing, etc.! Fire for Heraclitus, it is said = the principle of motion |and not simply fire|, something similar is fire in the teaching of Persian philosophy (and religion)! (362) If Heraclitus was the first to use the term λόγος (“word”) in the objective sense (law), this, too, is said to be taken from the Persian religion.... (364) — A quotation from the Zend-Avesta.[16] (367) In § 17 on the relation between Δίχη[17] and είμαρμένη, Lassalle interprets these ideas of Heraclitus in the sense of “ne- cessity,” “connection.” (376)
leged to express the Heraclitean philosophy when he says: “Necessity binds together the essential- ity of Being....” “Heraclitus is ... the source of the con- ception, common among the Stoics, that είμαρμένη rerum omnium necessitas,[18] ex- presses bond and ligation, illigatio....” (376) Cicero: “I, however, call fate what the Greeks call είμαρμένη, i.e., the order and sequence of causes, when one cause linked with another produces the phenomenon out of itself” (p. 377).
Speaking of “fire,” Lassalle proves, by repeating himself a thousand times over, that this is a “principle” for Heraclitus. He insists especially on the idealism of Heraclitus (p. 2 5—that the principle of development, des Werdens,[19] in Heracli- tus is logisch-präexistent,[20] that his phi- losophy = Idealphilosophie.[21] Sic!!) (p. 25). ((Squeezing into Hegelian!)) Heraclitus accepted “pure and absolute- ly immaterial fire” (p. 28 Timaeus, on Heraclitus).... On p. 56 (Vol. II) Lassalle introduces | ||||||||
a quotation |from Clemens Al.,[22] Stro-
mata V; Chapter 14| about Heraclitus, which, translated literally, reads: | ||||||||
“The world, an entity out of everything,
was created by none of the gods or men, but was, is and will be eternally living fire, regularly becoming ignited and reg- ularly becoming extinguished....” | NB | |||||||
A very good exposition of the principles
of dialectical materialism. But on p. 58 Lassalle provides the following “freie Über- setzung”[23] of this passage: “The world — — was, is and will be con- tinuous becoming, being constantly, but in varying measure, transformed from Being into (proceeding) not-Being, and from the latter into (proceeding) Being.” An excellent example how Lassalle verballhornt[24] Heraclitus, representing him as Hegelian, spoiling the liveliness, freshness, naïveté and historical integ- rity of Heraclitus by misrepresenting him as Hegelian (and in order to achieve this misrepresentation Lassalle presents a rehash of Hegel for dozens of pages). The second section of the second part (“Physics,” pp. 1 - 262!!!, Vol. II) is ab- solutely intolerable. A farthingsworth of Heraclitus, and a shillingsworth of rehash of Hegel and of misrepresentation. One can only leaf through the pages—in order to say that it should not be read! From Section III (“The Doctrine of Cog- nition”) a quotation from Philo: | ||||||||
“For the One is that which consists of
two opposites, so that when cut into two | NB | |||||||
the opposites are revealed. Is not this the
proposition which the Greeks say their great and famous Heraclitus placed at the head of his philosophy and gloried in as a new discovery....” ((265)) | NB | |||||||
And the following quotation also from
Philo: | ||||||||
...“In the same way, too, the parts of
the world are divided into two and mutual- ly counterposed: the earth—into moun- | ||||||||
tains and plains, water—into fresh and
salt.... In the same way, too, the atmos- phere into winter and summer, and like- | ||||||||
wise spring and autumn. And this served
Heraclitus as the material for his books on nature: borrowing from our theologian | NB | |||||||
the aphorism about opposites, he added | ||||||||
to it innumerable and laboriously worked-
out examples (Belege)” (p. 267). | ||||||||
According to Heraclitus the criterion
of truth is not the consensus omnium, not the agreement of all (p. 285)—in that case he would be a subjectiver Empiriker[25] (p. 284). No, he is an objectiver Idealist[26](285). For him, the criterion of truth, independent of the subjective opinion of all men, is agreement with the ideal law of the identity of Being and not-Being (285).
ner (note 1), Lassalle says that Her- aclitus expressed a priori “the very same thought” as “modern physiology” (“thought is a movement of matter”).
maeus): ...“Heraclitus, however, links our rea- son with the divine reason that guides and rules the world, and says that, on account of inseparable accompaniment, it, too, possesses knowledge of the governing decree of reason and, when the mind rests from the activity of the senses, it predicts the future” (p. 342). From Clemens (Stromata V.): ...“owing to its incredibility it—namely, the truth—escapes from becoming cog- nised....” (347) Heraclitus, Lassalle says, is “the father of objective logic” (p. 351), for in him “natural philosophy” umschlägt[28] into the philosophy of thought, “thought is recognised as the principle of existence” (350), etc., etc. à la Hegel.... The moment of subjectivity is said to be lacking in Heraclitus....
that in this dialogue of Plato’s Cratylus is represented (not yet as a sophist and subjectivist as he subsequently became, but) as a true disciple of Heraclitus, who really expounded his, Heraclitus’, theory of the essence and origin of words and language as an imitation of nature (“imitation of the essence of things,” p. 388), the essence of things, “the imitation and copy of God,” “imitation of God and the universe” (ibidem). |
Ergo:T h e h i s t o r y o f p h i l o s o p h y
” ” the mental development of the child ” ” the mental development of animals ” ” l a n g u a g e NB: + psychology + physiology of the sense o r g a n s | these are
the fields of knowlege from which the theory of knowl- edge and dialectics should be built
|
...“We have shown—says Lassalle—that
the” (above-mentioned) “conceptual iden- tity (precisely identity, and not merely analogy) between word, name and law is in every respect a principled view of the Heraclitean philosophy and of fundamental importance and significance in it....” (393) | ||||
...“Names are for him” (Heraclitus) “laws
of being, they are for him the common element of things, just as for him laws are the ‘common element of all’”.... (394) | NB | |||
And it is precisely Heraclilean ideas
that Hippocrates expresses when he says: “Names are the laws of nature.” | very
important! NB | |||
“For both laws and names are for the
Ephesian ... equally merely products and realisations of the universal, both are for him the achieved, purely universal, ideal being, freed from the stain of sensuous reality....” (394) Plato analyses and refutes the philos- ophy of Heraclitus in his “Cratylus” and “Theaetetus,” and in so doing (especially in the latter) he confuses Heracli- tus (the objective idealist and dialectician) with the subjective idealist and sophist Protagoras (man is the measure of all things). And Lassalle proves that in the development of ideas there has actually stemmed from Heraclitus 1) sophistry (Pro- tagoras) and 2) Platonism, the “ideas” (objective idealism).
(IV. Ethik, pp. 427-462.) In the section on ethics—nil. On pp. 458-459 Lassalle writes that Ne- mesios said that Heraclitus and Demo- critus denied prevision (προνοίαν), whereas Cicero (De Fato) said that Heraclitus, as also Democritus and others (including Aris- totle), recognised fatum—necessity. | ||||
...“This fatum is intended to signify only
the immanent natural necessity belonging to the object, its natural law....” (459) | Naturnot-
wendigkeit[31] in Lassalle | |||
(The Stoics, according to Lassalle, took
everything from Heraclitus, making him banal and one-sided, p. 461.)
correct, Lassalle’s book is not worth read- ing. |
- ↑ Hegel, Werke, Bd. XIII, Berlin, 1833.—Ed.
- ↑ Reference is being made to the conspectus of Hegel’s work Lectures on the History Of Philosophy, in which Lenin makes this quotation. (See p. 259 of this volume.)—Ed.
- ↑ Lenin is referring to a letter from Marx to Engels dated February 1, 1858 (see Marx and Engels, Selected Correspondence, Moscow, 1955, pp. 121-123).
- ↑ industrious—Ed.
- ↑ V. I. Lenin wrote the word “garlic” above the word “Knoblauch.”—Ed.
- ↑ evaporation—Ed.
- ↑ et. seq.—Ed.
- ↑ function of money—Ed.
- ↑ token of value—Ed.
- ↑ modern discoveries in this field—Ed.
- ↑ logos—Ed.
- ↑ necessity—Ed.
- ↑ the doctrine—Ed.
- ↑ the One Wise”—Ed.
- ↑ Ahriman—the Greek name for the ancient Persian God personifying the source of evil, an eternal and irreconcilable enemy of his brother Ormazd, the Good Spirit.
- ↑ Zend-Avesta—the designation for the ancient Persian religious books expounding the Zoroastrian religion founded, according to legend, by the prophet Zarathustra (Zoroaster).
- ↑ justice—Ed.
- ↑ necessity of all things—Ed.
- ↑ of becoming—Ed.
- ↑ logically pre-existent—Ed.
- ↑ idealistic philosophy—Ed.
- ↑ Clement of Alexandria—Ed.
- ↑ free translation—Ed.
- ↑ corrects (ironic)—Ed.
- ↑ subjective empiricist—Ed.
- ↑ objective idealist—Ed.
- ↑ Lenin is referring to Theses on Feuerbach by Marx written in 1845 (see Marx and Engels, Selected Works, Vol. II, Moscow, 1958, pp. 403-405).
- ↑ is transformed—Ed.
- ↑ Cratylus—Plato’s dialogue, directed against the Sophists.
- ↑ briefly—Ed.
- ↑ natural necessity—Ed.
- ↑ summa summarum—Ed.