Category | Template | Form |
---|---|---|
Text | Text | Text |
Author | Author | Author |
Collection | Collection | Collection |
Keywords | Keywords | Keywords |
Subpage | Subpage | Subpage |
Template | Form |
---|---|
BrowseTexts | BrowseTexts |
BrowseAuthors | BrowseAuthors |
BrowseLetters | BrowseLetters |
Template:GalleryAuthorsPreviewSmall
Special pages :
II. Saint Bruno
The Leipzig Council : II. Saint Bruno[edit source]
1. âCampaignâ Against Feuerbach[edit source]
Before turning to the solemn discussion which Bauerâs selfconsciousness has with itself and the world, we should reveal one secret. Saint Bruno uttered the battle-cry and kindled the war only because he had to âsafeguardâ himself and his stale, soured criticism against the ungrateful forgetfulness of the public, only because he had to show that, in the changed conditions of 1845, criticism always remained itself and unchanged. He wrote the second volume of the âgood cause and his own causeâ [Bruno Bauerâs article âCharakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachsâ is here ironically called the second volume of Bauerâs book Die gute.Sache der Freiheit und meine eigene Angelegenheit â The Good Cause of Freedom and My Own Cause]: he stands his ground, he fights pro aris et focis. [literally: for altars and hearths, used in the sense of: for house and home â that is, pleading his own cause] In the true theological manner, however, he conceals this aim of his by an appearance of wishing to âcharacteriseâ Feuerbach. Poor Bruno was quite forgotten, as was best proved by the polemic between Feuerbach and Stirner, [Feuerbach, âUeber das âWesen des Chrienthumsâ in Bezichung auf den âEinzigen und sein Eigenthum'"] which no notice at all was taken of him. For just this reason he seized on this polemic in order to be able to proclaim himself, as the antithesis of the antagonists, their higher unity, the Holy Spirit.
Saint Bruno opens his âcampaignâ with a burst of artillery fire against Feuerbach, that is to say, with a revised and enlarged reprint of an article which had already appeared in the Norddeutsche BlĂ€tter. [Bruno Bauerâs article âLudwig Feuerbach"] Feuerbach is made into a knight of âsubstanceâ in order that Bauerâs self-consciousnessâ shall stand out in stronger relief. In this trans-substantiation of Feuerbach, which is supposed to be proved by all the writings of the latter, our holy man jumps at once from Feuerbachâs writings on Leibniz and Bayle [The reference is to the following works of Feuerbach: Geschichte der neuern Philosophie. Darstellung, Entwirklung und Kritik der Leibnitzischen Philosophie and Pierre Bayle] to the Wesen des Christenthmus, leaving out the article against the âpositive philosophersâ,[1] in the Hallische JahrbĂŒcher. [Ludwig Feuerbach, âZur Kritik der âpositiven Philosophie'"] This âoversightâ is âin placeâ. For there Feuerbach revealed the whole wisdom of âselfconsciousnessâ as against the positive representatives of âsubstanceâ, at a time when Saint Bruno was still indulging in speculation on the immaculate conception.
It is hardly necessary to mention that Saint Bruno still continues to prance about on his old-Hegelian war horse. Listen to the first passage in his latest revelations from the Kingdom of God:
âHegel combined into one Spinozaâs substance and Fichteâs ego; the unity of both, the combination of these opposing spheres, etc., constitutes the peculiar interest but, at the same time, the weakness of Hegelâs philosophy. [... ] This contradiction in which Hegelâs system was entangled had to be resolved and destroyed. But he could only do this by making it impossible for all time to put the question: what is the relation of self-consciousness to the absolute spirit.... This was possible in two ways. Either self-consciousness had to be burned again in the flames of substance, i.e., the pure substantiality relation had to be firmly established and maintained, or it had to be shown that personality is the creator of its own attributes and essence, that it belongs to the concept of personality in general to posit itselfâ (the âconceptâ or the personality"?) âas limited, and again to abolish this limitation which it posits by its universal essence, for precisely this essence is only the result of its inner self-distinction of its activityâ (Wigand, pp. 86, 87, 88). [Bruno Bauer, âCharakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs"]
In Die Heilige Familie (p. 220 ) Hegelian philosophy was represented as a union of Spinoza and Fichte and at the same time the contradiction involved in this was emphasised. The specific peculiarity of Saint Bruno is that, unlike the authors of Die Heilige Familie, he does not regard the question of the relation of selfconsciousness to substance as âa point of controversy within Hegelian speculationâ, but as a world-historic, even an absolute question. This is the sole form in which he is capable of expressing the conflicts of the present day. He really believes that the triumph of selfconsciousness over substance has a most essential influence not only on European equilibrium but also on the whole future development of the Oregon problem[2]. As to the extent to which the abolition of the Corn Laws in England depends on it, very little has so far transpired.[3]
The abstract and nebulous expression into which a real collision is distorted by Hegel is held by this âcriticalâ mind to be the real collision itself. Bruno accepts the speculative contradiction and upholds one part of it against the other. A philosophical phrase about a real question is for him the real question itself. Consequently, on the one hand, instead of real people and their real consciousness of their social relations, which apparently confront them as something independent, he has the mere abstract expression: self-consciousness, just as, instead of real production, he has the activity of this self-consciousness, which has become independent. On the other hand, instead of real nature and the actually existing social relations, he has the philosophical summing-up of all the philosophical categories or names of these relations in the expression: substance; for Bruno, along with all philosophers and ideologists, erroneously regards thoughts and ideas â the independent intellectual expression of the existing world â as the basis of this existing world. It is obvious that with these two abstractions, which have become senseless and empty, he can perform all kinds of tricks without knowing anything at all about real people and their relations. (See, in addition, what is said about substance in connection with Feuerbach and concerning âhumane liberalismâ and the âholyâ in connection with Saint Max.) Hence, he does not forsake the speculative basis in order to solve the contradictions of speculation; he manoeuvres while remaining on that basis, and he himself still stands so much on the specifically Hegelian basis that the relation of âself-consciousnessâ to the âabsolute spiritâ still gives him no peace. In short, we are confronted with the philosophy of self-consciousness that was announced in the der Synoptiker, carried out in Das entdenckte Christenthum and which, unfortunately, was long ago anticipated in Hegelâs PhĂ€nomenologie. This new philosophy of Bauerâs was completely disposed of in Die Heilige Familie on page 220 et seq. and on pages 304-07. Here, however, Saint Bruno even contrives to caricature himself by smuggling in âpersonalityâ, in order to be able, with Stirner, to portray the single individual as âhis own productâ, and Stirner as Brunoâs product. This step forward deserves a brief notice.
First of all, let the reader compare this caricature with the original, the explanation given of self-consciousness in Das entdeckte Christenthum, page 113, and then let him compare this explanation with its prototype, with Hegelâs PhĂ€nomenologie, pages 575, 583 and so on. (Both these passages are reproduced in Die Heilige Familie, pages 221, 223, 224.) But now let us turn to the caricature! âPersonality in general"! âConcept"! âUniversal essence"! âTo posit itself as limited and again to abolish the limitation"! âInner self-distinction"! What tremendous âresults"! âPersonality âit generalâ is either nonsense âin generalâ or the abstract concept of personality. Therefore, it is part of the âconceptâ of the concept of personality to âposit itself as limitedâ. This limitation, which belongs to the âconceptâ of its concept, personality directly afterwards posits âby its universal essenceâ. And after it has again abolished this limitation, it turns out that âprecisely this essenceâ is âthe result of its inner self-distinctionâ. The entire grandiose result of this intricate tautology amounts, therefore, to Hegelâs familiar trick of the self-distinction of man in thought, a self-distinction which the unfortunate Bruno stubbornly proclaims to be the sole activity of âpersonality in generalâ. A fairly long time ago it was pointed out to Saint Bruno that there is nothing to be got from a âpersonalityâ whose activity is restricted to these, by now trivial, logical leaps. At the same time the passage quoted contains the naive admission that the essence of Bauerâs âpersonalityâ is the concept of a concept, the abstraction of an abstraction.
Brunoâs criticism of Feuerbach, insofar as It is new, is restricted to hypocritically representing Stirnerâs reproaches against Feuerbach and Bauer as Bauerâs reproaches against Feuerbach. Thus, for example, the assertions that the âessence of man is essence in general and something holyâ, that âman is the God of manâ, that the human species is âthe Absoluteâ, that Feuerbach splits man âinto an essential and an inessential egoâ (although Bruno always declares that the abstract is the essential and, in his antithesis of criticism and the mass, conceives this split as far more monstrous than Feuerbach does), that a struggle must be waged against the âpredicates of Godâ, etc. On the question of selfish and selfless love, Bruno, polemising with Feuerbach, copies Stirner almost word for word for three pages (pp. 133-35) just as he very clumsily copies Stirnerâs phrases: âevery man is his own creationâ, âtruth is a ghostâ, and so on. In addition, in Bruno the âcreationâ is transformed into a âproductâ. We shall return to this exploitation of Stirner by Saint Bruno.
Thus, the first thing that we discovered in Saint Bruno was his continual dependence on Hegel. We shall not, of course, dwell further on the remarks he has copied from Hegel, but shall only put together a few more passages which show how firmly he believes in the power of the philosophers and how he shares their illusion that a modified consciousness, a new turn given to the interpretation of existing relations, could overturn the whole hitherto existing world. imbued with this faith, Saint Bruno also has one of his pupils certify â in issue IV of Wigandâs quarterly, p. 327 â that his phrases on personality given above, which were proclaimed by him in issue III, were âworld-shattering ideasâ. ["Ueber das Recht des Freigesprochenen..."]
Saint Bruno says (Wigand, p. 95) [Bruno Bauer, âCharakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs"]
âPhilosophy has never been anything but theology reduced to its most general form and given its most rational expression.â
This passage, aimed against Feuerbach, is copied almost word for word from Feuerbachâs Philosophie der Zukunft (p. 2):
âSpeculative philosophy is true, consistent, rational theology.â
Bruno continues:
âPhilosophy, in alliance with religion, has always striven for the absolute dependence of the individual and has actually achieved this by demanding and causing the absorption of the individual life in universal life, of the accident in substance, of man in the absolute spirit.â
As if Brunoâs âphilosophyâ, âin alliance withâ Hegelâs, and his still continuing forbidden association with theology, did not âdemandâ, if not âcauseâ, the âabsorption of manâ in the idea of one of his âaccidentsâ, that of self-consciousness, as âsubstance"! Moreover, one sees from this whole passage with what joy the church father with his âpulpit eloquenceâ continues to proclaim his âworld-shatteringâ faith in the mysterious power of the holy theologians and philosophers. Of course, in the interests of the âgood cause of freedom and his own causeâ. [ironical allusion to Bauerâs book Die gute Sache der Freiheit und meine eigene Angelegenheit] On page 105 our god-fearing man has the insolence to reproach Feuerbach:
âFeuerbach made of the individual, of the depersonalised man of Christianity, not a man, not a trueâ (!) ârealâ (!!) âpersonalâ (!!!) âmanâ (these predicates owe their origin to Die Heilige Familie and Stirner), âbut an emasculated man, a slaveâ â
and thereby utters, inter alia, the nonsense that he, Saint Bruno, can make people by means of the mind. Further on in the same passage he says:
âAccording to Feuerbach the individual has to subordinate himself to the species, serve it. The species of which Feuerbach speaks is Hegelâs Absolute, and it, too, exists nowhere.â
Here, as in all the other passages, Saint Bruno does not deprive himself of the glory of making the actual relations of individuals dependent on the philosophical interpretation of these relations. He has not the slightest inkling of the correlation which exists between the concepts of Hegelâs âabsolute spiritâ and Feuerbachâs âspeciesâ on the one hand and the existing world on the other. On page 104 the holy father is mightily shocked by the heresy with which Feuerbach transforms the holy trinity of reason, love and will into something that âis in individuals and over individualsâ, as though, in our day, every inclination, every impulse, every need did not assert itself as a force âin the individual and over the individualâ, whenever circumstances hinder their satisfaction. If the holy father Bruno experiences hunger, for example, without the means of appeasing it, then even his stomach will become a force âin him and over himâ. Feuerbachâs mistake is not that he stated this fact but that in idealistic fashion he endowed it with independence instead of regarding it as the product of a definite and surmountable stage of historical development.
Page 111: âFeuerbach is a slave and his servile nature does not allow him to fulfil the work of a man, to recognise the essence of religionâ (what a fine âwork of a man"!)....... He does not perceive the essence of religion because he does not know the bridge over which he can make his way to the source of religion.â
Saint Bruno still seriously believes that religion has its own âessenceâ. As for the âbridgeâ, âover whichâ one makes oneâs way to the âsource of religionâ, this assesâ bridge [a pun in the original: EselsbrĂŒcke â assesâ bridge â an expedient used by dull or lazy people to understand a difficult problem] must certainly be an aqueduct. At the same time Saint Bruno establishes himself as a curiously modernised Charon who has been retired owing to the building of the bridge, becoming a toll-keeper who demands a halfpenny from every person crossing the bridge to the spectral realm of religion. On page 120 the saint remarks:
âHow could Feuerbach exist if there were no truth and truth were only a spectreâ (Stirner, help!') âof which hitherto man has been afraid?â
The âmanâ who fears the âspectreâ of âtruthâ is no other than the worthy Bruno himself. Ten pages earlier, on p. 110, he had already let out the following world-shattering cry of terror at the sight of the âspectreâ of truth:
âTruth which is never of itself encountered as a ready-made object and which develops itself and reaches unity only in the unfolding of personality.â
Thus, we have here not only truth, this spectre, transformed into a person which develops itself and reaches unity, but in addition this trick is accomplished in a third personality outside it, after the manner of the tapeworm. Concerning the holy manâs former love affair with truth, when he was still young and the lusts of the flesh still strong in him â see Die Heilige Familie, p. 115 et seq.' How purified of all fleshly lusts and earthly desires our holy man now appears is shown by his vehement polemic against Feuerbachâs sensuousness. Bruno by no means attacks the highly restricted way in which Feuerbach recognises sensuousness. He regards Feuerbachâs unsuccessful attempt, since it is an attempt to escape ideology, as â a sin. Of course! Sensuousness is lust of the eye, lust of the flesh and arrogance [cf. 1 John 2:16] â horror and abomination [cf. Ezekiel 11:18] in the eyes of the Lord! Do you not know that to be fleshly minded is death, but to be spiritually minded is life and peace; for to be fleshly, minded is hostility to criticism, and everything of the flesh is of this world. And do you not know that it is written: the works of the flesh are manifest, they are adultery, fornication, uncleanness, obscenity, idolatry, witchcraft, enmity, strife, envy, anger, quarrelsomeness, discord, sinful gangs, hatred, murder, drunkenness, gluttony and the like. [cf. Galatians 5:19-21] I prophesy to you, as I prophesied before, that those who do such works will not inherit the kingdom of criticism; but woe to them for in their thirst for delights they are following the path of Cain and are falling into the error of Balaam, and will perish in a rebellion, like that of Korah. These lewd ones feast shamelessly on your alms, and fatten themselves. They are clouds without water driven by the wind; bare, barren trees, twice dead and uprooted; wild ocean waves frothing their own shame; errant stars condemned to the gloom of darkness for ever. [cf. Jude 11-13] For we have read that in the last days there will be terrible times, people will appear who think much of themselves, lewd vilifiers who love voluptuousness [cf. 2 Timothy 3:1-4] more than criticism, makers of sinful gangs, in short, slaves of the flesh. Such people are shunned by Saint Bruno, who is spiritually minded and loathes the stained covering of the flesh [cf. Jude 23] and for this reason he condemns Feuerbach, whom he regards as the Korah of the gang, to remain outside together with the dogs, the magicians, the debauched and the assassins. [cf. Revelation 22:15] âSensuousnessâ â ugh! Not only does it throw the saintly church father into the most violent convulsions, but it even makes him sing, and on page 121 he chants the âsong of the end and the end of the songâ. Sensuousness â do you know, unfortunate one, what sensuousness is? Sensuousness is â a âstickâ (p. 130). Seized with convulsions, Saint Bruno even wrestles on one occasion with one of his own theses, just as Jacob of blessed memory wrestled with God, with the one difference that God twisted Jacobâs thigh, while our saintly epileptic twists all the limbs and ties of his own thesis, and so, by a number of striking examples, makes clear the identity of subject and object:
âFeuerbach may say what he likes ... all the same he destroysâ (!) âman... for he transforms the word man into a mere phrase ... for he does not wholly makeâ and createâ (!) âman, but raises the whole of mankind to the Absolute, for in addition he declares not mankind, but rather the senses to be the organ of the Absolute, and stamps the sensuous â the object of the senses, of perception, of sensation â as the Absolute, the indubitable and the immediately certain. Whereby Feuerbach â such is Saint Brunoâs opinion â âcan undoubtedly shake layers of the air, but he cannot smash the phenomena of human essence, because his innermostâ (!) âessence and his vitalising spirit [...] already destroys the externalâ (!) âsound and makes it empty and jarringâ (p. 121).
Saint Bruno himself gives us mysterious but decisive disclosures about the causes of his nonsensical attitude:
âAs though my ego does not also possess just this particular sex, unique, compared with all others, and these particular, unique sex organs,â (Besides his âunique sex organsâ, this noble-minded man also possesses a special âunique sex"!)
This unique sex is explained on page 121 in the sense that:
âsensuousness, like a vampire, sucks all the marrow and blood from the life of man; it is the insurmountable barrier against which man has to deal himself a mortal blowâ.
But even the saintliest man is not pure! They are all sinners and lack the glory that they should have before âself-consciousnessâ. Saint Bruno, who in his lonely cell at midnight struggles with âsubstanceâ, has his attention drawn by the frivolous writings of the heretic Feuerbach to women and female beauty. Suddenly his sight becomes less keen; his pure self-consciousness is besmirched, and a reprehensible, sensuous fantasy plays about the frightened critic with lascivious images. The spirit is willing but the flesh is weak. [cf. Matthew 26:41] Bruno stumbles, he falls, he forgets that he is the power that âwith its strength binds, frees and dominates the worldâ, [cf. ibid. 16:19] he forgets that these products of his imagination are âspirit of his spiritâ, he loses all âself-controlâ and, intoxicated, stammers a dithyramb to female beauty, to its âtenderness, softness, womanlinessâ, to the âfull and rounded limbsâ and the âsurging, undulating, seething, rushing and hissing, wave-like structure of the bodyâ of woman. Innocence, however, always reveals itself â even where it sins. Who does not know that a âsurging, undulating, wave-like structure of the bodyâ is Something that no eye has ever seen, or ear heard? Therefore â hush, sweet soul, the spirit will soon prevail over the rebellious flesh and set an insurmountable âbarrierâ to the overflowing, seething lusts, âagainst whichâ they will soon deal themselves a âmortal blowâ.
âFeuerbachâ â the saint finally arrives at this through a critical understanding of Die Heilige Familie â âis a materialist tempered with and corrupted by humanism, i.e., a materialist who is unable to endure the earth and its beingâ (Saint Bruno knows the being of the earth as distinct from the earth itself, and knows how one should behave in order to âendure the being of the earth"!) âbut wants to spiritualism himself and rise into heaven; and at the same time he is a humanist who cannot think and build a spiritual world, but one who is impregnated with materialismâ, and so on (p. 123).
Just as for Saint Bruno humanism, according to this, consists in thinkingâ and in âbuilding a spiritual worldâ, so materialism consists in the following:
âThe materialist recognises only the existing, actual being, matterâ (as though man with all his attributes, including thought, were not an âexisting, actual beingâ), âand recognises it as actively extending and realising itself in multiplicity, natureâ (p. 123).
First, matter is an existing, actual being, but only in itself, concealed; only when it âactively extends and realises itself in multiplicityâ (an âexisting, actual beingâ ârealises itself"!!), only then does it become nature. First there exists the concept of matter, an abstraction, an idea, and this latter realises itself in actual nature. Word for word the Hegelian theory of the pre-existence of the creative categories. From this point of view it is understandable that Saint Bruno mistakes the philosophical phrases of the materialists concerning matter for the actual kernel and content of their world outlook.
2. Saint Brunoâs Views on the Struggle Between Feuerbach and Stirner[edit source]
Having thus admonished Feuerbach with a few weighty words, Saint Bruno takes a look at the struggle between Feuerbach and the unique. The first evidence of his interest in this struggle is a methodical, triple smile.
âThe critic pursues his path irresistibly, confident of victory, and victorious. He is slandered â he smiles. He is called a heretic â he smiles. The old world starts a crusade against him â he smiles.â
Saint Bruno â this is thus established â pursues his path but he does not pursue it like other people, he follows a critical course, he accomplishes this important action with a smile.
âHe does smile his face into more lines than are in the new map, with the augmentation of the Indies. 1 know my lady will strike him: if she do, he'll smile and take it for a great art, [Shakespeare, Twelfth Night, Act III, Scene 2. Marx and Engels quote these lines front the German translation by August Wilhelm von Schlegel. But they have substituted the word Kunst (art) for the word Gunst (favour)] â like Shakespeareâs Malvolio.
Saint Bruno himself does not lift a finger to refute his two opponents, he knows a better way of ridding himself of them, he leaves them â divide et impera â to their own quarrel. He confronts Stirner with Feuerbachâs man (p. 124), and Feuerbach with Stirnerâs unique (p. 126 et seq.); he knows that they are as incensed against each other as the two Kilkenny cats in Ireland, which so completely devoured each other that finally only their tails remained. [4] And Saint Bruno passes sentence on these tails, declaring that they are âsubstanceâ and, consequently, condemned to eternal damnation.
In confronting Feuerbach with Stirner he repeats what Hegel said of Spinoza and Fichte, where, as we know, the punctiform ego is represented as one, and moreover the most stable, aspect of substance. However much Bruno formerly raged against egoism, which he even considered the odor specificus of the masses, on page 129 he accepts egoism from Stirner â only this should be ânot that of Max Stirnerâ, but, of course, that of Bruno Bauer. He brands Stirnerâs egoism as having the moral defect âthat his ego for the support of its egoism requires hypocrisy, deception, external violenceâ. For the rest, be believes (see p. 124) in the critical miracles of Saint Max and sees in the latterâs struggle (p. 126) âa real effort to radically destroy substanceâ. Instead of dealing with Stirnerâs criticism of Bauerâs âpure criticismâ, he asserts on p. 124 that Stirnerâs criticism could affect him just as little as any other, âbecause he himself is the criticâ.
Finally Saint Bruno refutes both of thein, Saint Max and Feuerbach, applying almost literally to Feuerbach and Stirner the antithesis drawn by Stirner between the critic Bruno Bauer and the dogmatist.
Wigand, p. 138: âFeuerbach puts himself in opposition to, and therebyâ (!) âstands in opposition to, the unique. He is a communist and wants to be one. The unique is an egoist and has to he one; he is the holy one, the other the profane one, he is the good one, the other the evil one, he is God, the other is man. Both are dogmatists.â
The point is, therefore, that he accuses both of dogmatism.
Der Einzige und sein Eigenthum, p. 194: âThe critic is afraid of becoming dogmatic or of putting forward dogmas. Obviously, he would then become the opposite of a critic, a dogmatist; he who as a critic was good, would now become evil, or from being unselfishâ (a Communist) âwould become an egoist, etc. Not a single dogma! â that is his dogma.â
3. Saint Bruno Versus the Authors of Die Heilige Familie[edit source]
Saint Bruno, who has disposed of Feuerbach and Stirner in the manner indicated and who has âcut the unique off from all progressâ, now turns against the apparent âconsequences of Feuerbachâ, the German Communists and, especially, the authors of Die Heilige Familie. The expression âreal humanismâ, which he found in the preface to this polemic treatise, provides the main basis of his hypothesis. He will recall a passage from the Bible:
âAnd I, brethren, could not speak unto you as unto spiritual, but as unto carnalâ (in our case it was just the opposite), âeven as unto babes in Christ. I have fed you with milk, and not with meat: for hitherto ye were not able to bear itâ (1 Corinthians, 3: 1-2).
The first impression that Die Heilige Familie made on the worthy church father was one of profound distress and serious, respectable sorrow. The one good side of the book is that it
âshowed what Feuerbach had to become, and the position his philosophy can adopt, if it desires to fight against criticismâ (p. 138),
that, consequently, it combined in an easy-going way âdesiringâ with âwhat can beâ and âwhat must heâ, but this good side does not out-weigh its many distressing sides. Feuerbachâs philosophy, which strangely enough is presupposed here,
âdare not and cannot understand the critic, dare not and cannot know and perceive criticism in its development, dare not and cannot know that, in relation to all that is transcendental, criticism is a constant struggle and victory, a continual destruction and creation, the soleâ (!) âcreative and productive principle. It dare not and cannot know how the critic has worked, and still works, to posit and to makeâ (!) âthe transcendental forces, which up to now have suppressed mankind and not allowed it to breathe and live, into what they really are, the spirit of the spirit, the innermost of the innermost, a native thingâ (!) âout of and in the native soil, products and creations of self-consciousness. It dare not and cannot know that the critic and only the critic has smashed religion in its entirety, and the state in its various manifestations, etc.â (pp. 138,139).
Is this not an exact copy of the ancient Jehovah, who runs after his errant people who found greater delight in the cheerful pagan gods, and cries out:
âHear me, Israel, and close not your ear, Judah! Am I not the Lord your God, who led you out of the land of Egypt into the land flowing with milk and honey, and behold, from your earliest youth you have done evil in my sight and angered me with the work of my hands and turned your back unto me and not your face towards me, though 1 invariably tutored you; and you have brought abominations into my house to defile it, and built the high places of Baal in the valley of the son of Himmon, which 1 did not command, and it never entered my head that you should do such abominations; and 1 have sent to you my servant Jeremiah, to whom I did address my word, beginning with the thirteenth year of the reign of King Josiah, son of Amon, unto this day â and for twenty-three years now he has been zealously preaching to you, but ye have not harkened. Therefore says the Lord God: Who has ever heard the like of the virgin of Israel doing such an abomination. For rain water does not disappear so quickly as my people forgets me. 0 earth, earth, earth, hear the word of the Lord!â [cf. Jeremiah 2:6, 32:22, 30, 33-35, 25:3, 19:3, 18:13, 14, 22:29]
Thus, in a lengthy speech on âto dareâ and âto be ableâ, Saint Bruno asserts that his communist opponents have misunderstood him. The way in which he describes criticism in this recent speech, the way in which he transforms the former forces that suppressed â,the life of mankindâ into âtranscendental forcesâ, and these transcendental forces into the âspirit of the spiritâ, and the way in which he presents âcriticismâ as the sole branch of production proves that the apparent misconception is nothing but a disagreeable conception. We proved that Bauerâs criticism is beneath all criticism, owing to which we have inevitably become dogmatists. He even in all seriousness reproaches us for our insolent disbelief in his ancient phrases. The whole mythology of independent concepts, with Zeus the Thunderer â self-consciousness â at the head, is paraded here once again to the âjingling of hackneyed phrases of a whole janissary band of current categoriesâ. (Literatur-Zeitung, cf. Die Heilige Familie, p. 234). First of all, of course, the myth of the creation of the world, i.e., of the hard â1abourâ of the critic, which is âthe sole creative and productive principle, a constant struggle and victory, a continual destruction and creationâ, âworkingâ and âhaving workedâ. Indeed, the reverend father even reproaches Die Heilige Familie for understanding âcriticismâ in the same way as he understands it himself in the present rejoinder. After taking back âsubstanceâ âinto the land of its birth, self-consciousness, the criticising andâ (since Die Heilige Familie also) âthe criticised man, and discarding itâ (self-consciousness here seems to take the place of an ideological lumber-room), he continues:
âItâ (the alleged philosophy of Feuerbach) âdare not know that criticism and the critics, as long as they have existedâ (!)"have guided and made history, that even their opponents and all the movements and agitations of the present time are their creation, that it is they alone who hold power in their hands, because strength is in their consciousness, and because they derive power from themselves, from their deeds, from criticism, fromâ their opponents, from their creations; that only by the act of criticism is man freed. and thereby men also, and man is createdâ (!) âand thereby mankind as wellâ.
Thus, criticism and the critics are first of all two wholly different subjects, existing and operating apart from each other. The critic is a subject different from criticism, and criticism is a subject different from the critic. This personified criticism, criticism as a subject, is precisely that â critical criticismâ against which Die Heilige Familie was directed. âCriticism and the critics, as long as they have existed, have guided and made history.â It is clear that they could not do so âas long as theyâ did not âexistâ, and it is equally clear that âas long as they have existedâ they âmade historyâ in their own fashion. Finally, Saint Bruno goes so far as to âdare and be ableâ to give us one of the most profound explanations about the state-shattering power of criticism, namely, that âcriticism and the critics hold power in their hands, becauseâ (a fine âbecause"!) âstrength is in their consciousnessâ, and, secondly, that these great manufacturers of history âhold power in their handsâ, because they âderive power from themselves and from criticismâ (i.e., again from themselves) â whereby it is still, unfortunately, not proven that it is possible to âderiveâ anything at all from there, from âthemselvesâ, from âcriticismâ. On the basis of criticismâs own words, one should at least believe that it must be difficult to âderiveâ from there anything more than the category of âsubstanceâ âdiscardedâ there. Finally, criticism also âderivesâ âfrom criticismâ âpowerâ for a highly monstrous oracular dictum. For it reveals to us a secret that was hidden [cf. Colossians 1 :26] from our fathers and unknown to our grandfathers, the secret that âonly by the act of criticism is man created, and thereby mankind as wellâ â whereas, up to now, criticism was erroneously regarded as an act of people who existed prior to it owing to quite different acts. Hence it seems that Saint Bruno himself came âinto the world, from the world, and to the worldâ through âcriticismâ, i.e., by generatio aequiioca [spontaneous generation]. All this is, perhaps, merely another interpretation of the following passage from the Book of Genesis: And Adam knew, i.e., criticised, Eve his wife: and she conceived, [cf. Genesis 4: 1] etc.
Thus we see here the whole familiar critical criticism, which was already sufficiently characterised in Die Heilige Familie, confronting us again with all its trickery as though nothing had happened. There is no need to be surprised at this, for the saint himself complains, on page 140, that Die Heilige Familie âcuts criticism off from all progressâ. With the greatest indignation Saint Bruno reproaches the authors of Die Heilige Familie because, by means of a chemical process, they evaporated Bauerâs criticism from its âfluidâ state into a crystallineâ state.
It follows that âinstitutions of mendicancyâ, the âbaptismal certificate of adulthoodâ, the âregions of pathos and thunder-like aspectsâ, the âMussulman conceptual afflictionâ (Die Heilige Familie, pp. 2, 3, 4 according to the critical Literatur-Zeitung) â all this is nonsense only if it is understood in the âcrystallineâ manner. And the twenty-eight historical howlers of which criticism was proved guilty in its excursion on âEnglische Tagesfragenâ [article by Julius Faucher] â are they not errors when looked at from the âfluidâ point of view? Does criticism insist that, from the fluid point of view, it prophesied a priori the Nauwerck conflict [5] â long after this had taken place before its eyes â and did not construct it post festum? Does it still insist that the word marichal could mean âfarrierâ from the âcrystallineâ point of view, but from the âfluidâ point of view at any rate must mean marshal"? Or that although in the âcrystallineâ conception âun fait physiqueâ may mean âa physical factâ, the true âfluidâ translation should be âa fact of physics"? Or that âla malveillance de nos bourgeois juste-milieuxâ [the ill will of our middle-of-the-road bourgeois] in the âfluidâ state still means âthe care-freeness of our good burghers"? Does it insist that, from the âfluidâ point of view, âa child that does not, in its turn, become a father or mother is essentially a daughter"? That someone can have the task âof representing, as it were, the last tear of grief shed by the past"? That the various concierges, lions, grisettes, marquises, scoundrels and wooden doors in Paris in their âfluidâ form are nothing but phases of the mystery âin whose concept in general it belongs to posit itself as limited and again to abolish this limitation which is posted by its universal essence, for precisely this essence is only the result of its inner self-distinction, its activity"[Bruno Bauer, âCharakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs"]? That critical criticism in the âfluidâ sense âpursues its path irresistibly, victorious and confident of victoryâ, when in dealing with a question it first asserts that it has revealed its âtrue and general significanceâ and then admits that it âhad neither the will nor the right to go beyond criticismâ, and finally admits that âit had still to take one step but that step was impossible because â it was impossibleâ (Die Heilige Familie, p. 184)? That from the âfluidâ point of view âthe future is still the workâ of criticism, although âfate may decide as it willâ [B. Bauer, âNeueste Schriften Ăber die Judenfrage"]? That from the fluid point of view criticism achieved nothing superhuman when it âcame into contradiction with its true elements â a contradiction which had already found its solution in these same elements [ B. Bauer, âWas ist jetzt der Gegenstand der Kritik?"]?
The authors of Die Heilige Familie have indeed committed the frivolity of conceiving these and hundreds of other statements as statements expressing firm, âcrystallineâ nonsense â but the synoptic gospels should be read in a âfluidâ way, i.e., according to the sense of their authors. and on no account in a âcrystallineâ way, e., according to their actual nonsense, in order to arrive at true faith and to admire the harmony of the critical household.
âEngels and Marx, therefore, know only the criticism of the Literatur-Zeitungâ [Bruno Bauer, âCharakteristik Ludwig Feuerbachs"]
â a deliberate lie, proving how âfluidlyâ our saint has read a book in which his latest works are depicted merely as the culmination of all the âwork he has doneâ. But the church father lacked the calm to read in a crystalline way, for he fears his opponents as rivals who contest his canonisation and âwant to deprive him of his sanctity, in order to make themselves sanctifiedâ.
Let us, incidentally, note the fact that, according to Saint Brunoâs present statement, his Literatur-Zeitung by no means aimed at founding âsocial societyâ or at ârepresenting, as it were, the last tear of griefâ shed by German ideology, nor did it aim at putting mind in the sharpest opposition to the mass and developing critical criticism in all its purity, but only â at âdepicting the liberalism and radicalism of 1842 and their echoes in their half-heartedness and phrase-mongeringâ, hence at combating the âechoesâ of what has long disappeared. Tant de bruit pour une omelette! [Much ado about an omelette! An exclamation which Jacques VallĂ©, Sieur des Barreaux, is supposed to have made when a thunderstorm occurred while he was eating an omelette on a fast-day] Incidentally, it is just here that the conception of history peculiar to German theory is again shown in its âpurestâ light. The year 1842 is held to be the period of the greatest brilliance of German liberalism, because at that time philosophy took part in politics. Liberalism vanishes for the critic with the cessation of the Deutsche JahrbĂŒcher and the Rheinische Zeitung, the organs of liberal and radical theory. After that, apparently, there remain only the âechoesâ â whereas in actual fact only now, when the German bourgeoisie feels a real need for political power, a need produced by economic relations, and is striving to satisfy has liberalism in Germany an actual existence and thereby 1 the chance of some success.
Saint Brunoâs profound distress over Die Heilige Familie did not allow him to criticise this work âout of himself, through himself and with himselfâ. To be able to master his pain he had first to obtain the work in a âfluidâ form. He found this fluid form in a confused review, teeming with misunderstandings, in the WestphĂ€lische Dampfboot, May issue, pp. 206-14 All his quotations are taken from passages quoted in the WestphĂ€lische Dampfboot and he quotes nothing that is not quoted there.
The language of the saintly critic is likewise determined by the language of the Westphalian critic. In the first place, all the statements from the Foreword which are quoted by the Westphalian (Dampfboot, p. 206) are transferred to the Wigandâsche Vierteljahrsschrift (pp. 140, 141). This transference forms the chief part of Bauerâs criticism, according to the old principle already recommended by Hegel:
âTo trust common sense and, moreover, in order to keep up with the times and advance with philosophy, to read reviews of philosophical works, perhaps even their prefaces and introductory paragraphs; for the latter give the general principles on which everything turns, while the former give, along with the historical information, also an appraisal which, because it is an appraisal, even goes beyond that which is appraised This beaten track can be followed in oneâs dressing-gown; but the elevated feeling of the eternal, the sacred, the infinite, pursues its path in the vestments of a high priest, a pathâ which, as we have seen, Saint Bruno also knows how to âpursueâ while âstriking downâ (Hegel, PhĂ€nomenologie, p. 54).
The Westphalian critic, after giving a few quotations from the preface, continues:
âThus the preface itself leads to the battlefield of the bookâ, etc. (p. 206).
The saintly critic, having transferred these quotations into the Wigandâsche Vierteljahrsschrift, makes a more subtle distinction and says:
âSuch is the terrain and the enemy which Engels and Marx have created for battle.â
From the discussion of the critical proposition: âthe worker creates nothingâ, the Westphalian critic gives only the summarising conclusion.
The saintly critic actually believes that this is all that was said about the proposition, copies out the Westphalian quotation on page 141 and rejoices at the discovery that only âassertionsâ have been put forward in opposition to criticism.
Of the examination of the critical outpourings about love, the Westphalian critic on page 209 first writes out the corpus delicti in part and then a few disconnected sentences from the refutation, which he desires to use as an authority for his nebulous, sickly-sweet sentimentality.
On pages 141-42 the saintly critic copies him out word for word, sentence by sentence, in the same order as his predecessor quotes.
The Westphalian critic exclaims over the corpse of Herr Julius Faucher: âSuch is the fate of the beautiful on earth!â. [Schiller. Wallensteinâs Tod, Act IV, Scene 12]
The saintly critic cannot finish his âhard workâ without appropriating this exclamation to use irrelevantly on page 142.
The Westphalian critic on page 212 gives a would-be summary of the arguments which are aimed against Saint Bruno himself in Die Heilige Familie.
The saintly critic cheerfully and literally copies out all this stuff together with all the Westphalian exclamations. He has not the slightest idea that nowhere in the whole of this polemic discourse does anyone reproach hint for âtransforming the problem of political emancipation into that of human emancipationâ, for âwanting to kill the Jewsâ, for âtransforming the Jews into theologiansâ, for âtransforming Hegel into Herr Hinrichsâ, etc. Credulously, the saintly critic repeats the Westphalian criticâs allegation that in Die Heilige Familie Marx volunteers to provide some sort of little scholastic treatise âin reply to Bauerâs silly self-apotheosisâ. Yet the words âsilly self-apotheosisâ, which Saint Bruno gives as a quotation, are nowhere to be found in the whole of Die Heilige Familie, but they do occur with the Westphalian critic. Nor is the little treatise offered as a reply to the âself-apologyâ of criticism on pages 150-63 of Die Heilige Familie, but only in the following section on page 165, in connection with the world-historic question: âWhy did Herr Bauer have to engage in politics?â
Finally on page 143 Saint Bruno presents Marx as an âamusing comedianâ, here again following his Westphalian model, who resolved the âworld-historic drama of critical criticismâ, on page 213, into a âmost amusing comedyâ.
Thus one sees how the opponents of critical criticism âdare and canâ âknow how the critic has worked, and still works"!
4. Obituary For âM. Hessâ[edit source]
âWhat Engels and Marx could not yet do, M. Hess has accomplished.â
Such is the great, divine transition which â owing to the relative âcanâ and âcannotâ be done of the evangelists â has taken so firm a hold of the holy manâs fingers that it has to find a place, relevantly or irrelevantly, in every article of the church father.
âWhat Engels and Marx could not yet do, M. Hess has accomplished.â But what is this âwhatâ that âEngels and Marx could not yet do"? Nothing more nor less, indeed, than â to criticise Stirner. And why was it that Engels and Marx âcould not yetâ criticise Stirner? For the sufficient reason that â Stirnerâs book had not yet appeared when they wrote Die Heilige Familie.
This speculative trick â of joining together everything and bringing the most diverse things into an apparent causal relation â has truly taken possession not only of the head of our saint but also of his fingers. With him it has become devoid of any contents and degenerates into a burlesque manner of uttering tautologies with an important mien. For example, already in the Allgemeine Literatur-Zeitung (1, 5) we read:
âThe difference between my work and the pages which, for example, a Philippson covers with writingâ (that is, the empty pages on which, âfor example, a Philippsonâ writes) âmust, therefore, be so constituted as in fact it is"!!! [Bauer, âNeueste Schriften ĂŒber die Judenfrage"]
âM. Hessâ, for whose writings Engels and Marx take absolutely no responsibility, seems such a strange phenomenon to the saintly critic that he is only capable of copying long excerpts from Die letzten Philosophen and passing the judgment that âon some points this criticism has not understood Feuerbach or alsoâ (O theology!) âthe vessel wishes to rebel against the potterâ. Cf. Epistle to the Romans, 9: 20-21. Having once more performed the âhard workâ of quoting, our saintly critic finally arrives at the conclusion that Hess copies from Hegel, since he uses the two words âunitedâ and âdevelopmentâ. Saint Bruno, of course, had in a round-about way to try to turn against Feuerbach the proof given in Die Heilige Familie of his own complete dependence on Hegel. âSee, that is how Bauer had to end! He fought as best he could against all the Hegelian categoriesâ, with the exception of selfconsciousness â particularly in the glorious struggle of the Literatur-Zeitung against Herr Hinrichs. How he fought and conquered them we have already seen. For good measure, let us quote Wigand, page 110, where he asserts that
the âtrueâ (1) âsolutionâ (2) âof contradictionsâ (3) âin nature and historyâ (4), the âtrue unityâ (5) âof separate relationsâ (6), the âgenuineâ (7) âbasisâ (8) âand abyssâ (9) âof religion, the truly infiniteâ (10), âirresistible, self-creativeâ (11) âpersonalityâ (12) âhas not yet been foundâ.
These three lines contain not two doubtful Hegelian categories, as in the case of Hess, but a round dozen of âtrue, infinite, irresistibleâ Hegelian categories which reveal themselves as such by â,the true unity of separate relationsâ â âsee, that is how Bauer had to end"! And if the holy man thinks that in Hess he has discovered a Christian believer, not because Hess âhopesâ â as Bruno says â but because he does not hope and because he talks of the âresurrectionâ, then our great church father enables us, on the basis of this same page 1 10, to demonstrate his very pronounced Judaism. He declares there
âthat the true, living man in the flesh has not yet been born"!!! (a new elucidation about the determination of the âunique sexâ) âand the mongrel producedâ (Bruno Bauer?!?) âis not yet a le to master all dogmatic formulasâ, etc.
That is to say, the Messiah is not yet born, the son of man has first to come into the world and this world, being the world of the Old Testament, is still under the rod of the law, of âdogmatic formulasâ. Just as Saint Bruno, as shown above, made use of âEngels and Marxâ for a transition to Hess, so now the latter serves him to bring Feuerbach finally into causal connection with his excursions on Stirner, Die heilige Familie and Die letzten Philosophen.
âSee, that is how Feuerba.ch had to end!â âPhilosophy had to end piouslyâ, etc. (Wigand, p. 145.)
The true causal connection, however, is that this exclamation is an imitation of a passage from Hessâ Die letzten Philosophen aimed against Bauer, among others (Preface, p. 4):
âThus, [... ] and in no other way had the last offspring of the Christian ascetics to take farewell of the world.â
Saint Bruno ends his speech for the prosecution against Feuerbach and his alleged accomplices with the reproach to Feuerbach that all he can do is to âtrumpetâ, to âblow blasts on a trumpetâ, whereas Monsieur B. Bauer or Madame la critique, the âmongrel producedâ, to say nothing of the continual âdestructionâ, âdrives forth in his triumphal chariot and gathers new triumphsâ (p. 125), âhurls down from the throneâ (p. 119), âslaysâ (p. 111), âstrikes down like thunderâ (p. 115), âdestroys once and for allâ (p. 120), âshattersâ (p. 121), allows nature merely to âvegetateâ (p. 120), builds âstricterâ (!) âprisonsâ (p. 104) and, finally, with âcrushingâ pulpit eloquence expatiates, on p. 105, in a brisk, pious, cheerful and free ["Brisk, pious, cheerful and freeâ (âfrisch, fromm, fröhlich und freiâ) â the initial words of a studentsâ saying, which were turned by Ludwig Jahn into the motto of the sport movement he initiated] fashion on the âstably-strongly-firmly-existingâ, hurling ârock-like matter and rocksâ at Feuerbachâs head (p. 110) and, in conclusion, by a side thrust vanquishes Saint Max as well, by adding âthe most abstract abstractnessâ and âthe hardest hardnessâ (on p. 124) to âcritical criticismâ, âsocial societyâ and ârock-like matter and rocksâ.
All this Saint Bruno accomplished âthrough himself, in himself and with himselfâ, because he is âHe himselfâ; indeed, he is âhimself always the greatest and can always be the greatestâ (is and can be!) âthrough himself, in himself and with himselfâ (p. 136). Thatâs that.
Saint Bruno would undoubtedly be dangerous to the female sex, for he is an âirresistible personalityâ, if âin the same measure on the other handâ he did not fear âsensuousness as the barrier against which man has to deal himself a mortal blowâ. Therefore, âthrough himself, in himself and with himselfâ he will hardly pluck any flowers but rather allow them to wither in infinite longing and hysterical yearning for the âirresistible personalityâ, who âpossesses this unique sex and these unique, particular sex organsâ.
[The following passage is crossed out in the manuscript:]
5. Saint Bruno in His âTriumphal Chariotâ[edit source]
Before leaving our church father âvictorious and confident of victoryâ, let us for a moment mingle with the gaping crowd that comes up running just as eagerly when he âdrives forth in his triumphal chariot and gathers new triumphsâ as when General Tom Thumb with his four ponies provides a diversion. It is not surprising that we hear the humming of street-songs, for to be welcomed with street-songs âbelongs after all to the conceptâ of triumph âin generalâ.
- â Positive philosophyâ â a mystical religious trend (Christian Hermann Weisse, Immanuel Hermann Fichte Junior, Anton GĂŒnther, Franz Xaver von Baader, and Friedrich Schelling in his late period), which criticised Hegelâs philosophy from the right. The âpositive philosophersâ tried to make philosophy subservient to religion, denied the possibility of rational cognition and proclaimed divine revelation the only source of âpositiveâ knowledge. They called ânegativeâ every philosophy which recognised rational cognition as its source
- â Oregon was claimed by both the U.S.A. and Britain. The struggle for the possession of Oregon ended in June 1846 with the division of the territory between the U.S.A. and Britain.
- â The Anti-Corn Law League was founded in 1838 by the Manchester manufacturers Cobden and Bright. The English Corn Laws, first adopted in the 15th century, imposed high tariffs on imported cereals in order to maintain high prices for them in the home market. In the first third of the 19th century, in 1815, 1822 and later, several laws were passed changing the conditions for corn imports, and in 1828 a sliding scale was introduced which raised import tariffs on corn when prices in the home market declined and, on the other hand, lowered tariffs when prices rose in Britain. The League widely exploited the popular discontent over the raising of corn prices. In its efforts to obtain the repeal of the Corn Laws and the establishment of complete freedom of trade, it aimed at weakening the economic and political positions of the landed aristocracy and lowering the cost of living thus making possible a lowering of the workersâ wages. The struggle between the industrial bourgeoisie and the landed aristocracy over the Corn Laws ended with the repeal of these laws in 1846.
- â The expression âto fight like Kilkenny catsâ originated at the end of the 18th century. During the Irish uprising of 1798 the town of Kilkenny was occupied by Hessian mercenaries serving in the British army, who used to amuse themselves by watching fights between cats with their tails tied together. One day, a soldier, seeing an officer approaching, cut off the catsâ tails with his sword and the cats ran away. The officer was told that the cats had eaten each other and only their tails remained
- â An allusion to the conflict between the Young Hegelian Karl Nauwerck and the professors of the Faculty of Philosophy at Berlin University (see Chapter III of The Holy Family, the MECW, Vol. 4, pp. 17-18)